Thursday, March 20, 2014
with,only,as,much,intervention,as,is,necessary,to,facilitate,her,decisions,For,retarded,persons,who,cannot,make,their,own,decisions
STERILIZATION
OF MENTALLY
RETARDED
PERSONS:
REPRODUCTIVE
RIGHTS
AND FAMILY PRIVACY
ELIZABETH
S. ScoTr*
Sterilization
is one of the most
frequently
chosen forms
of contra-
ception
in the world;
1
many persons
who do not
want to have children
select this simple,
safe, and effective
means
of avoiding unwanted
preg-
nancy.
For individuals
who are mentally
disabled,
however, sterilization
has
more ominous
associations.
Until recently,
involuntary sterilization
was used
as a weapon
of the state in
the war against
mental deficiency.
Under
eugenic sterilization
laws
in effect in many
states, retarded
persons
were
routinely
sterilized
without
their
consent
or
knowledge.
* Associate Professor
and Director, Center for the Study of
Children and the Law, University
of Virginia
School of Law. J.D. 1977,
University of Virginia.
My interest
in the impact of the
sterilization reform
laws on families arose
out of my association
with the Forensic Psychiatry
Clinic at the
University of Virginia,
an interdisciplinary
clinic associ-
ated with the
Law School and
Medical School. This
clinic has frequently
conducted psychological
evaluations of
mentally disabled persons whose parents
sought sterilization under Virginia's reform
law. My observation
of these individuals
and their families
has influenced my
thinking on these
issues. Several examples
in this article
are taken from
Forensic Psychiatry
Clinic cases.
I would
like to thank
my colleagues Kenneth
Abraham, Richard
Bonnie, Nancy
Ehrenreich,
Gary Melton,
John Monahan, Gary Peller, and Walter
Wadlington for their helpful comments
on
earlier drafts
of this article. Special
thanks are due
to Robert Scott. I
also thank Cathy Basham,
John D'Amico, Margaret
Rice, and Amy Nickell for
research assistance.
1. See Isaacs, Reproductive
Rights-1983:
An International
Survey, 14 COLUM.
HuM. RTs. L.
REv. 311, 328 (1983)
(90 to 100 million
couples worldwide
choose sterilization
as a method of
contraception).
In the United
States, sterilization
is the most popular
form of birth control
for
couples over
thirty, and it rivals the Pill as a method
of contraception for all couples.
Id.
Salpingectomy
(tubal ligation)
is a surgical procedure
by which the
fallopian tubes are
tied and
severed. There are many different
methods of performing tubal ligation,
ranging from abdominal
incisions to
laparoscopy, a microsurgical
procedure.
See R. HATCHER, F.
GUEST, F. STEWART,
G.
STEWART,
J. TRUSSELL, S.
CEREL & W. CATES,
CONTRACEPTIVE
TECHNOLOGY 1986-1987,
at
283-93 (1986) [hereinafter
CONTRACEPTIVE
TECHNOLOGY].
Vasectomy, the most
effective means of
male fertility control,
is a surgical excision
of the vas deferens
(a duct that carries
sperm). Id. at 104,
281-83.
2. For a discussion
of the eugenic sterilization
movement
of the early twentieth
century, see
infra notes
10-13 and accompanying
text. See
generally Lombardo,
Three Generations,
No Imbe-
ciles, New Light
on Buck v. Bell,
60 N.Y.U. L. REV.
30, 31 (1985). It is
estimated that almost
64,000
persons had been involuntarily
sterilized
under state eugenic sterilization
laws by
1963. The
practice was most prevalent
in California (20,108 sterilizations),
Virginia (7162 sterilizations), and
North
Carolina (6297 sterilizations).
EUGENIC
STERILIZATION
app. at 1 (J. Robitscher
ed. 1973).
In Conservatorship
of Valerie N., 40
Cal. 3d 143, 152,
707 P.2d 760, 765, 219
Cal. Rptr. 387, 392
(1985),
the California Supreme
Court noted that
California led the
nation in eugenic sterilization.
This factor may
have influenced the
legislature's enactment
of a law barring
the sterilization of
2
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
Sterilization law has undergone a radical transformation in recent
years.
3
Influenced
by a distaste for eugenic
sterilization and a desire
to
redress past injustices, the emerging
law seeks to protect
the interests of
mentally disabled persons by
erecting formidable barriers
to sterilization.
The policy goals of this reform
movement are commendable.
However,
in its
singleminded effort to prevent
erroneous sterilizations, the
law departs
from
what would be its underlying
objectives: to protect where
possible the individual's
right to make her
4
own reproductive
decisions
and to ensure
that any decision made
by others will best protect her
interests.
Current law purports
to protect the individual's
reproductive rights,
but the focus
is one-sided. Although the
law protects the "right to procreate,"
it does so by unnecessarily
burdening the reciprocal
right not to
procreate. The option of sterilization-seen
as a legitimate
exercise of
the right of reproductive privacy
when chosen by the normal
person-
may be unavailable
to the retarded person. Despite
rhetorical emphasis
on the importance
of reproductive autonomy,
the paternalistic stance
of
the law improperly limits the
freedom of some persons who
may be capable
of
making
their own reproductive
choices. In many states,
only a
court acting
as decisionmaker is deemed
capable of protecting disabled
persons from those
who would violate
their rights.
The assumption
that the law's overriding
purpose is to protect the
right to procreate
arises from the historical
and political context of the
incompetents. CAL. PROB. CODE
§ 2356(d) (1981). This statutory provision
was struck down in
Valerie N.
3. The
sterilization law reform movement
is largely embodied in a series of judicial
opinions
beginning in 1980 with the Washington
Supreme Court case of In re Guardianship
of Hayes, 93
Wash. 2d 228, 239, 608 P.2d
635, 641 (1980). See infra notes 33-36
and accompanying text. See
also
Ruby v. Massey, 452 F. Supp. 361, 369
(D. Conn. 1978); In re C.D.M., 627 P.2d
607, 614
(Alaska 1981); Valerie
N., 40 Cal. 3d at 160, 707 P.2d at 771-72,
219 Cal. Rptr. at 399; In re A.W.,
637 P.2d 366, 370 (Colo. 1981);
Wentzel v. Montgomery Gen. Hosp.,
Inc., 293 Md. 685, 703, 447
A.2d
1244, 1254 (1982), cert. denied, 459 U.S.
1147 (1983); In re Moe, 385 Mass. 555,
559, 432
N.E.2d 712, 716 (1982); In re
Penny N., 120 N.H. 269, 271-72, 414
A.2d 541, 543 (1980); In re
Grady,
85 N.J. 235, 258-62, 426 A.2d 467, 479-81
(1981); In re Sallmaier, 85 Misc. 2d 295,
297, 378
N.Y.S.2d
989, 991 (Sup. Ct. 1976); In re Terwilliger,
304 Pa. Super. 553, 564-68, 450
A.2d 1376,
1382-84 (1982);
In re Guardianship of Eberhardy, 102
Wis. 2d 539, 578-79, 307 N.W.2d 881,
899
(1981). Several states have enacted reform
statutes in recent years. See CONN.
GEN. STAT. ANN.
§ 45-78y(b) (West Supp. 1986);
ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 34-B, §§ 7001-7017
(Supp. 1986); OR.
REv. STAT.
§ 436.305(3) (1983); UTAH CODE ANN.
§ 64-10-8(4) (1986); VT. STAT. ANN. tit.
18,
§ 8705 (Supp.
1986); VA. CODE ANN. §§ 54-325.10 to
.12 (1982). For a discussion of the reform
laws, see infra notes 31-58 and accompanying text.
4. This
article uses the feminine pronoun
to refer to the mentally retarded person
for whom
sterilization
is proposed because it appears that the issue
arises much more frequently with females
than with males. For example,
all cases cited supra note 3 involved females.
Furthermore, some of
the analysis, such as that involving
the intrusiveness of hysterectomy, applies
only to females. None-
theless, much of the analysis applies to both males and females.
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
reform
movement.
It is
not based
on a careful
analysis
of the
retarded
person's
interest
in reproductive
autonomy
and
how
this
interest
may
be
affected
by
her
disability.
There
is an
understandable
reluctance
to
un-
dertake
such
analysis;
even
asking
the
question
implies
differences
in the
interests
of retarded
and
nonretarded
people.
However,
the
failure
to
discern
the
actual
interests
at
stake
can
lead
to
erroneous
decisions
contrary
to
the
normative
objective
of the
law.
This
article
focuses
on
parents'
efforts
to
obtain
sterilization
of
their
mentally
retarded
children.
As
a result
of the
trend
toward
deinstitutionalization,
a
growing
number
of
mentally
disabled
individuals
live
with
their
parents.
Because
current
law
reacts
primarily
to
the
state's
historical
wrongful
treatment
of
institutionalized
persons,
5
it is
not
sufficiently
responsive
to
the
needs
of retarded
individuals
who
live
with
their
families.
6
Part
I of
the
article
describes
the
current
law
and
explores
how
its
paternalistic
approach
fails
to protect
the
interests
of
mentally
disabled
persons
when
their
parents
propose
sterilization.
7
Part
II
develops
an
alternative
approach,
which
I will
call
the
"autonomy
model.
This
model
is developed
primarily
through
an
analysis
of the
effects
of mental
disability
on
three
dimensions
of the
disabled
person's
reproductive
interest-avoiding
unwanted
pregnancy,
having
children,
and
making
auton-
omous
choices.
Part
III
explores
the
implications
of
the
autonomy
model
for
the
formulation
of
an
optimal
sterilization
rule.
The
model
suggests
that
the
law
should
maximize
individual
and
family
autonomy
and
minimize
paternalistic
intervention
by
the
state.
The
goal
of
protecting
the
retarded
person's
interests
is
largely
achieved
by
choosing
the
appropriate
decisionmaker;
in
most
cases
this
will
be
the
individual
herself
or
her
parents.
Under
this
approach,
the
court's
role
in
most
cases
is
limited
to
deciding
whether
the
individual
has
the
capacity
to
make
her
own
choices
or whether
her
parents
must
make
the
decision
for her.
5.
Many
eugenic
sterilization
laws,
directed
toward
institutionalized
patients,
authorized
the
director
of
such
facilities
to
make
the
decision
or
to petition
a court.
In
Ruby
v. Massey,
452 F.
Supp.
361
(D. Conn.
1978),
a Connecticut
law
that
permitted
sterilization
only of
mentally
disabled
individuals
in institutions
was
struck
down
on
equal
protection
grounds.
Id.
at 367-69.
Some
laws
required
sterilization
as a precondition
to release
from
state
institutions.
See,
e.g.,
Buck
v.
Bell,
274
U.S. 200,
204 (1927).
6. Indeed,
most of
the judicial
opinions
developing
the paternalism
model
involved
efforts
by a
parent
or
guardian
to sterilize
a child
cared
for
at home.
See,
e.g.,
In re
Grady,
85
N.J.
235,
240-42,
251,
426
A.2d
467, 469-70,
475 (1981);
In re
Sallmaier,
85
Misc.
2d
295, 296-97,
378 N.Y.S.2d
989,
989-90
(Sup.
Ct.
1976).
7. See
infra
notes
10-61
and accompanying
text.
8.
See
infra
notes
62-139
and
accompanying
text.
9. See
infra
notes
140-80
and
accompanying
text.
9
[Vol. 1986:806
' 8
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
I. CURRENT STERILIZATION
LAW: A PATERNALISM
MODEL
A. The Context of Reform.
Three factors have
stimulated and shaped the
reform of sterilization
law:
the discrediting of the eugenic
theory, the development of
the constitutional
doctrine of
reproductive privacy, and the
changing conception
of mental retardation.
The
vigilant stance
of current law
is largely a re-
sponse to the unsavory history
of eugenic sterilization in
this country.
During the first
half of this century, laws in many
states authorized sterilization
of
mentally deficient persons and
others believed to be societal
burdens."
These laws were
based largely
on eugenic theory,
which enjoyed
considerable
popularity in the progressive
era. The theory posited
that intelligence
and most personality traits are
genetically based and are
predictably
inherited by children
from their parents.
12
The objective
of
10. See In re Moe,
385 Mass. 555, 559,
432 N.E.2d 712, 717
(1982) ("We are
well aware of the
sordid
history of compulsory eugenic sterilization
laws in the United States."); Grady,
85 N.J. at
245,
426 A.2d at 472 ("[W]e have serious doubts
about the scientific validity of eugenic
sterilization.");
In re Guardianship
of Hayes,
93 Wash. 2d 228, 236,
608 P.2d 635, 640
(1980) ("[T]he
theoretical
foundation for eugenic sterilization
as a method of improving society has
been disproved.").
Rejection of compulsory
sterilization laws on scientific and social
policy grounds has had
broad support in the legal literature since
the 1960's. See Burgdorf & Burgdorf,
The Wicked Witch
is Almost Dead: Buck v. Bell
and the Sterilization of Handicapped Persons,
50 TEMP. L.Q. 995,
1033-34 (1977);
Ferster, Eliminating
the Unfit-Is Sterilization
the Answer?,
27 OHIO ST. L.J.
591,
619-25 (1966);
Murdock, Sterilization
of the Retarded:
A Problem or a Solution?,
62 CALIF. L.
REV.
917, 934-35
(1974); Sherlock & Sherlock, Sterilizing
the Retarded: Constitutional, Statutory,
and
Policy Alternaties, 60 N.C.L. REV. 943, 980-83 (1982).
11. Sterilization
laws were directed at the mentally
retarded, mentally ill, epileptic, and criminal
populations. Indiana passed the
first involuntary sterilization law in 1907.
Act of March 9,
1907,
ch. 215, 1907 IND.
AcTs 377 (repealed
1963). By 1925, twenty-three
states had passed
eugenic
sterilization laws. Cynkar, Buck v. Bell:
"Felt Necessities" v. Fundamental Values?,
81 COLUM. L.
REV. 1418, 1433 (1981). As late as 1966,
twenty-six states had eugenic sterilization
laws. Ferster,
supra note 10,
at 596. State courts often upheld sterilization
laws using two police power justifica-
tions-that of preventing
the birth of defective children and
that of lowering the public welfare
expense of supporting
children whose parents could
not support them. See In re Simpson,
180
N.E.2d 206,
208 (Ohio P. Ct. 1962);
Ferster, supra note 10, at 609.
Some
sterilization laws were used to punish
habitual criminals and rapists. A Washington
stat-
ute authorizing
the sterilization of convicted rapists was
upheld in State v. Feilen, 70 Wash. 65,
66,
126 P.
75, 76 (1912). The United States Supreme
Court, however, struck down an Oklahoma
statute
allowing sterilization
of habitual criminals in Skinner v. Oklahoma
ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535,
542-43
(1942). Some statutes had paternalistic
objectives and authorized sterilization if
it was in the
best interest of
the individual and
society. Virginia's sterilization
statute was
enacted in part
to
alleviate fears that institutionalized
individuals returning to society would
produce children. See
Act of March 20, 1924, ch. 394, 1924
VA. AcTs 569, 569 (amended and
rec6dified 1968).
12. The
eugenic movement
was an outgrowth
of Mendelian genetics.
The eugenicists,
building
upon Mendel's
findings about
the hereditability
of physical traits, argued
that intelligence,
personality,
and
even character traits such as dishonesty,
criminality, and laziness were directly
"transmit-
ted." See H. LAUGHLIN,
EUGENIC STERILIZATION IN
THE UNITED STATES 369 (1922).
Furthermore,
certain traits were associated with racial
or national groups. Id. at 372-92 (listing
"human
traits which have been shown to follow
definite rules of inheritance"). This view
served as
the basis
for the Nazi eugenic policies. The
accepted view was that defectives were
reproducing
10
DUKE LAW
JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
the eugenic
sterilization
laws was
to protect and
improve society
by
preventing
reproduction
by
those
who
might
produce
defective
off-
spring.
1
3
In
1927,
the Supreme
Court
in
Buck
v. Bell
14
upheld
Virginia's
ster-
more quickly
than normal
people,
thus posing
a
significant
threat
to society.
For an
excellent
historical
account
of
the
eugenic
movement,
see
Cynkar,
supra
note
11, at
1420-35.
13.
See H.
LAUGHLIN,
supra
note
12, at 369
("[D]efectives
who
are
practically
certain
to
breed
principally
defectives,
owe a
debt to
the community
that
can be
discharged
only by
an adequate
guarantee
that
they shall
not
contribute
to the
next generation.").
The
following
quote
reveals
the
threat
to society
that
eugenicists
thought
the mentally
retarded
posed:
The
past few
years have
witnessed
a striking
awakening
of professional
and
popular
consciousness
of the
widespread
prevalence
of feeblemindedness
and its
influence
as
a
source-of
wretchedness
to
the patient
himself
and
to his
family,
and as
a causative
factor
in
the production
of crime,
prostitution,
pauperism,
illegitimacy,
intemperance,
and
other
complex
social
diseases....
The
feebleminded
are a
parasitic,
predatory
class,
never
capa-
ble
of self-support
or of managing
their
own affairs....
They
cause unutterable
sorrow
at
home
and are
a menace
and
danger
to
the community
....
Feebleminded
women
are
almost
invariably
immoral
and if
at large
usually
become
carriers
of venereal
disease
or
give
birth
to children
who
are as
defective
as themselves....
Every feebleminded
person,
especially
the
high-grade
imbecile,
is a potential
criminal,
needing
only the
proper
environment
and
opportunity
for
the development
and
expression
of
his criminal
tendencies.
S.
DAviEs,
SOCIAL
CONTROL
OF THE
FEEBLEMINDED
56
(1923), quoted
in
Cynkar,
supra note
11,
at 1424-25.
A,1934
law review
note,
arguing
for
a sterilization
law
in Kentucky,
also reflects
this perception
of
societal
threat:
"Since
time
immemorial,
the criminal
and defective
have
been
the 'cancer
of
society.'
Strong,
intelligent,
useful
families
are becoming
smaller
and smaller;
while
irresponsible,
diseased,
defective
families
are becoming
larger.
The
result
can only
be race
degeneration."
Note, A
Sterilization
Statute
for
Kentucky?,
23 Ky.
L.J.
168, 168
(1934),
quoted
in Burgdorf
& Burgdorf,
supra
note
10, at 998.
14.
274
U.S.
200, 207
(1927).
Prior
to
Buck
v. Bell,
most
courts
struck
down
sterilization
statutes
as unconstitutional.
See
Davis
v. Berry,
216
F. 413,
417 (S.D.
Iowa
1914)
(cruel
and
unu-
sual
punishment
grounds),
rev'd
as moot,
242
U.S. 468
(1917);
Williams
v. Smith,
190 Ind.
526,
528,
131
N.E. 2, 2
(1921)
(due process
grounds);
Haynes
v.
Lapeer,
201 Mich.
138,
145, 166
N.W.
938,
941
(1918)
(equal
protection
grounds);
see
also
Burgdorf
& Burgdorf,
supra
note
10, at
1000-01
nn.44-48;
Ferster,
supra
note
10,
at 593-94
nn.1
1-12.
Buck
Y. Bell
is often
cited
to
illustrate
the
abuses
of eugenic
sterilization
policy.
Bell
was
the
test case
for Virginia's
new sterilization
law. Carrie
Buck
was
a 17 year-old
girl
who
had been
committed
to
a state
institution
for the
epileptic
and feebleminded
after
giving birth
to an
illegitimate
daughter.
The Virginia
law
required
that
institutionalized
patients
be sterilized
for
eugenic
and
therapeutic
reasons
as
a condition
of
release.
See Cynkar,
supra
note
11, at 1437-38.
Subsequent
historical
research
has suggested
that neither
Carrie,
her mother,
nor
Carrie's
daughter
(who
was an
infant
at the
time
of the
"diagnosis")
were "imbeciles"
as
characterized
by Justice
Holmes
in his
much quoted
proclamation,
"[t]hree
generations
of imbeciles
are
enough."
Bell,
274 U.S.
at 207.
Indeed,
it has been
reported
that
Carrie's
daughter
was on
the second
grade
honor
roll before
dying
at age eight.
See
Lombardo,
supra
note
2, at 61.
It seems
probable
that the
moralistic
impulses
of
the
eugenicists
influenced
the
categorization
of this family
as
feebleminded.
See
Cynkar,
supra
note
11,
at 52-53.
Carrie
and
her mother
both
produced
children
out of
wedlock.
The
testimony
of Dr.
Priddy,
the
director
of the
institution,
also suggests
that
sterilization
was
viewed
as a way
to achieve
social
control
over the
poor:
"[Tihese
people
belong
to the shiftless,
ignorant,
and worthless
class
of
anti-social
whites
of the
South
... [about
whom]
it
is impossible
to get
intelligent
and
satisfactory
data ....
" Lombardo,
supra note
2, at
51-52.
See also
Cynkar,
supra note
1i,
at 1439
(discussing
use of sterilization
as
method
for controlling
poverty).
This
harsh
tone
may
obscure
the fact
that
eugenic
policies
were
not
viewed
as
oppressive
in-
fringements
on individual
rights,
but as tools
of social
reform.
Eugenicists
attributed
most
social
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
ilization
law against constitutional
challenge and implicitly accepted
the
validity of eugenic
theory. Even at that time,
however, the scientific
merit of the
theory was controversial;'
5
it has since been largely discredited.
16
Reports of widespread
sterilization in Nazi Germany
led to increased
criticism
of eugenic sterilization
laws. By the 1960's, involuntary
sterilization
was frequently characterized
as an unjustified intrusion
by
the state on individual liberty
and privacy.
1 7
The reform
law that has
problems to heredity; they linked
crime, prostitution, and poverty to mental
deficiency. Progressives
therefore embraced these policies as state
action designed to improve society, arguing
that if afflicted
individuals
were prevented from reproducing,
society's ills would disappear. Justice
Holmes was
articulating the accepted
liberal view in endorsing the
eugenic rationale.
15. See Cynkar, supra note 11, at
1420-35. It appears, though, that Buck's
attorney, White-
head, never fully briefed this
issue for argument before the Court. It
was only in the petition for
rehearing (following a storm
of public protest over Holmes's opinion)
that Whitehead included the
strongest
arguments against the sterilization law-questioning
for the first time the "scientific"
pro-
positions
espoused by eugenic theories. Some
have pointed to this sequence of events to
support the
allegation that Bell was
a "friendly suit." Lombardo,
supra note 2, at 57.
16. Researchers
in genetics increasingly disassociated
themselves from the eugenic movement
as scientific
understanding of genetics became
more sophisticated in the 1920's and 1930's.
In 1936,
the American Neurological Association
Committee for the Investigation
of Eugenical Sterilization
issued a statement opposing
eugenic sterilization and challenging
its scientific premises. See Ferster,
supra note 10, at 602-03. In
1937, a committee of the American Medical
Association also adopted
this position.
Id. at 603. The critical scientific fallacy
underlying the sterilization laws is that "conditions
such as feeblemindedness
lump together cases having
no genetic component with those in
which there may be a partial
or complete genetic contribution." Moorhead,
Views of a Geneticist on
Eugenic
Sterilization, in EUGENIC
STERILIZATION,
supra note 2, at
115. For an interesting
history
of the eugenics movement,
see Kevles, The Annals of Eugenics,
NEW YORKER, Oct. 8, 1984, at 51;
Oct. 15, 1984, at 52;
Oct. 22, 1984, at 92; Oct.
29, 1984, at 51.
This is not to say that intelligence does
not have a hereditary component. Most
modern experts
agree that genetic factors
significantly influence intelligence and
that there is, in general, a relationship
between
children's
and
parents' intelligence.
Scarr-Salapatek, Genetics
and the Development
of
Intelligence, 4
CHILD DEV. RES. 1
(1975). Psychological
studies indicate that
both heredity and
environment can influence
intelligence. The most impressive evidence
for some genetic determina-
tion
of intelligence comes from studies of adopted
children. Professor Munzinger critically
evaluated
studies of adopted children and found
that five studies (involving 351 families)
showed that the
average
correlation between the parents' and
their adopted children's IQs was 0.19.
B. MARTIN,
ABNORMAL
PSYCHOLOGY 567 (1977). He found
a significantly greater correlation between
the intelligence
level of the same
children and their biological
parents. Id
17. The development
of the doctrine of reproductive privacy
in the 1960's and 1970's has affected
the
constitutional analysis of sterilization
laws. Since eugenic sterilization laws
infringe a
fundamental
right, these laws are subject to strict scrutiny
rather than the rational-basis review
engaged in by Justice
Holmes in Bell. See Roe v. Wade, 410
U.S. 113, 155 (1973); Skinner v.
Oklahoma ex
rel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942).
The Virginia statute in Bell probably would
not meet this
heightened scrutiny given the dubious
validity of eugenic theory. Indeed, several
courts
authorizing parens
patriae sterilization
have assumed that Bell
is constitutionally
suspect. See
In re A.W., 637 P.2d 366, 368
(Colo. 1981); In re Grady, 85 N.J. 235,
246, 426 A.2d 467, 472
(1981).
Even if the state could establish
that involuntary sterilization was necessary
to promote a compelling
state
interest, the statute
in Bell might fall under the "least restrictive
alternative" doctrine.
In Shelton v.
Tucker, 364 U.S. 479 (1960), the Supreme
Court stated this doctrine as follows: "Even
though the governmental purpose
be legitimate and substantial, that purpose
cannot be pursued by
means
that broadly stifle fundamental personal
liberties when the end can be more
narrowly
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
emerged
in recent
years represents
a vehement
rejection of the
philoso-
phy and policy of the eugenic movement.'
8
It is explicitly designed to
protect the interests of the retarded person rather than those of society.
A second impetus to reform has been the development of the consti-
tutional doctrine of reproductive privacy.'
9
A principal reason why
courts and legislatures have been concerned about protecting the repro-
ductive rights of retarded persons
20
is that reproductive rights in general
achieved. The breadth of legislative abridgment must be viewed in the light of less drastic means for
achieving the same basic purpose." Id. at 488 (footnote omitted). See generally Hoffmann & Faust,
Least Restrictive Treatment of the Mentally IlI: A Doctrine in Search of Its Senses, 14 SAN DIEO L.
REv. 1100 (1977).
Numerous commentators have criticized eugenic sterilization and Justice Holmes's opinion in
Bell from a
constitutional perspective. See Sherlock
& Sherlock, supra note 10, at 954; Zenoff,
Reappraisal of Eugenic Sterilization Laws, 10 CLEV.-MARSHALL L. REV. 149, 159-60 (1961); Note,
Eugenic Sterilization
Statutes: A Constitutional Re-Evaluation,
14 J. FAM. L. 280, 297 (1975).
18. Twenty-eight eugenic sterilization statutes were reported in 1956. See O'Hara & Sanks,
Eugenic Sterilization, 45 GEO. L.J. 20,42 (1956). Many of these have been repealed since the 1960's.
See CAL. WELF. & INST. CODE § 7254 (West Supp. 1972) (repealed 1972); ME. REV. STAT. ANN.
tit. 34, § 2462 (1978) (repealed 1981); OKLA. STAT. ANN. tit. 43A, § 341 (West 1979) (repealed
1983). Today only a few states have police-power sterilization laws. See Miss. CODE ANN. § 41-45-
1 (1972); N.C. GEN. STAT. § 35-36 (1984); S.C. CODE ANN. § 44-47-10 (Law. Co-op. 1976); W. VA.
CODE § 27-16-1 (1980).
19. A series of Supreme Court opinions beginning with Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479,
485 (1965) (striking down law
banning use of contraceptives), developed
the modem doctrine of
reproductive privacy. Several decisions have struck down restrictions on the use and sale of contraceptives
and on a woman's right to choose abortion. See, e.g., Thornburgh v. American College of
Obstetricians & Gynecologists, 106 S. Ct. 2169, 2182 (1986) (women have constitutionally protected
right to abortion; state regulation may not intimidate women into continuing pregnancies); City of
Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, Inc., 462 U.S. 416, 452 (1983) (city cannot impose
restrictive
requirements on abortion or determine
that all minors under age 15 are too
immature to
make abortion decision); Bellotti v. Baird, 443 U.S. 622, 651 (1979) (plurality opinion) (mature
minors
have right to make abortion decisions
without parental consent); Carey v. Population
Servs.
Int'l, 431 U.S. 678, 694 (1977) (law prohibiting sale of contraceptives to anyone under age 16 re-
stricts
reproductive privacy); Planned Parenthood
v. Danforth, 428 U.S. 52, 69-70 (1976)
(states
cannot give husband or parents veto over wife's or daughter's abortion decision by requiring con-
sent); Roe, 410 U.S. at 164-66 (women have right to terminate pregnancy through abortion until
viability); Doe v. Bolton, 410 U.S. 179, 201 (1973) (requirement that abortions be performed in
hospitals and approved by a hospital committee unduly restricts reproductive privacy); Eisenstadt v.
Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 443 (1972) (making contraceptives unavailable to single women infringes reproductive
privacy).
Aside from the uncertain scientific basis of eugenic theories, there has been a vehement rejection
on ethical grounds of the policy that less intelligent members of society should not be allowed to
reproduce.
20. The judicial opinions dealing with
parens patriae sterilization repeatedly
emphasize the im-
portance of protecting the retarded person's constitutional right of reproductive privacy. See Conservatorship
of Valerie N., 40 Cal. 3d 143, 161, 707 P.2d 760, 772, 219 Cal. Rptr. 387, 399 (1985)
(incompetent women have procreative choice that is recognized as fundamental right); see also In re
Moe, 385 Mass. 555, 563-64, 432 N.E.2d 712, 719 (1982) (decision to bear child at heart of constitu-
tionally protected right to privacy); Grady,
85 N.J. at 250, 426 A.2d at 474 (inability
to make reproductive
decisions
should not result in forfeiture of constitutional right); In re Guardianship of Hayes,
93 Wash. 2d 228, 234, 608 P.2d 635, 639 (1980) (sterilization implicates right to privacy and fundamental
right to procreate).
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
have been
accorded a special status in recent
years. The right of normal
adults and mature minors
2
to avoid unwanted pregnancy
through abortion,
contraception,
and (for adults) sterilization
22
is well established.
The
right to procreate, in contrast,
has received little attention,
probably
because it
has seldom been challenged.
2 3
The development of the doctrine
of reproductive
privacy casts substantial
doubt on the continued
validity of involuntary
sterilization laws like the one
upheld in Buck v.
Bell.
24
There is
general consensus that mentally
disabled persons should,
to the extent
that their disability allows,
enjoy the same right of repro-
ductive
privacy
as
normal
people.
25
21. See
supra note
19.
22. The Supreme
Court has not addressed the issue
of the right of normal adults to obtain
sterilization.
Lower courts, however, have expanded
the right of reproductive privacy to
include the
right to obtain sterilization.
See Hathaway v. Worcester City
Hosp., 475 F.2d 701, 706 (1st Cir.
1973) (hospital policy
banning sterilization violates equal protection
clause because surgical proce-
dures of equal risk are
permitted); Ponter v. Ponter, 135 N.J. Super.
50, 55, 342 A.2d 574, 577 (1975)
(married
woman has constitutional right to
obtain sterilization without husband's
consent).
Normal minors are generally not permitted to obtain sterilization. See, e.g., COLo. REV. STAT.
§ 27-10.5-128(1) (1982);
VT. STAT. ANN. tit. 18, § 8705(a) (Supp.
1986). The enormous cost of error
justifies
some restriction on reproductive autonomy.
Unlike abortion and contraception,
the minor
can postpone the sterilization decision with minimal cost.
23. See Robertson, Procreative Liberty
and the Control of Conception, Pregnancy,
and Childbirth,
69
VA. L. REV. 405, 406
(1983). Professor Robertson provides
a comprehensive analysis of
the right to procreate in the context
of modem reproductive technology. He
defines three dimen-
sions
of the right-conception,
gestation and birth, and
rearing.
The only Supreme Court decision that
specifically affirms the right to procreate
is Skinner v.
Oklahoma ex reL Williamson,
316 U.S. 535 (1942). The Court
did not analyze the substance of the
right
but described it as essential to
the "survival of the race." Id.
at 541.
24. Nonetheless, constitutional
analysis of the reform law
is complicated by two factors. The
application of the doctrine of reproductive
privacy to persons with questionable
capacity for autono-
mous decisionmaking
is unclear to the extent that the right of
reproductive privacy is the right to
control
reproductive decisions. Furthermore,
unlike eugenic law, the reform law is designed
to pro-
mote the mentally retarded person's interest
(by making the option of sterilization
available); it is not
inherently an infringement by the state
on a fundamental right. As noted above,
the right to choose
sterilization is itself
constitutionally protected. See supra note
22. Thus the application of strict
scrutiny is unclear.
25. Reform advocates tend to define
the retarded person's interest in reproductive
privacy
solely in terms
of the right to procreate. In Foy v. Greenblott,
141 Cal. App. 3d 1, 9-10, 190
Cal.
Rptr. 84, 90
(1983), a severely retarded woman became
pregnant and had a child. She sued
her
conservator for negligence
in failing to prevent the pregnancy
and birth through contraception or
abortion. The court rejected
the claim on the ground that her conservator
would have interfered
with her right
of reproductive privacy by taking such
measures. Id at 9, 190 Cal. Rptr. at 89-90.
Many courts that have examined sterilization laws have likewise emphasized the disabled wo-
man's
fundamental right to procreate. See In
re Truesdell, 63 N.C. App. 258, 267, 304
S.E.2d 793,
799 (1983) ("[S]terilization
not only affects the individual's
fundamental right to procreate....
it
forever deprives the individual of that basic liberty."). In Conservatorship of Valerie N., 40 Cal. 3d
143,
707 P.2d 760, 219 Cal. Rptr. 387 (1985),
Chief Justice Bird, dissenting, argued to uphold
Cali-
fornia's statutory
ban on the sterilization of individuals
under a conservatorship on the grounds
of
the right
to procreate. Id., at 183, 707 P.2d
at 788, 219 Cal. Rptr. at 415 (Bird, C.J.,
dissenting).
Bird
argued that the mentally disabled person
does not have the right to be sterilized
because that
right is premised
on the ability to make a decision. Id.
According to Bird, the mentally disabled
DUKE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 1986:806
The
view that the
mentally retarded
person
should exercise
her
rights
to the fullest
extent possible
reflects a
changing conception
of
mental
retardation.
A cognitive
developmental
approach
has
to some
extent supplanted
the medical
model of
mental retardation
that empha-
sizes
unalterable
organic
brain pathology.
26
With the
application
of cog-
nitive
developmental
theory
to
the functioning
of
mentally
retarded
persons,
there has
been a corresponding
appreciation
that
the designation
"mentally
retarded"
applies
to
individuals
who
exhibit
a
broad
range
of
deficiencies.
2
7
person
does have
an unrestricted
right to procreate,
because
she has the
right to retain
"the biological
capabilities
with which...
she was born into this
world." Id. at 181,
707 P.2d at 786, 219
Cal.
Rptr. at
413. See generally
Price &
Burt, Sterilization,
State Action
and the Concept
of Consent,
1 L.
& PSYCHOLOGY
REV. 57,
63-65 (1975)
(characterizing
third-party
consent to sterilization
as a
deprivation
of
the
individual's
rights).
Some
laws assume that
the retarded person's
interest in reproductive
choice is like
that of the
normal person,
and that
the law's role
is to remove
the barrier created
by her
disability. The
New
Jersey
Supreme Court
articulated
this view: "Lee
Ann does not
have the ability
to make
a choice
between
sterilization and
procreation ....
But her inability should
not result in the
forfeit of this
constitutional
interest ....
[T]he decision
. . . 'should
not be discarded
solely
on the basis that
her
condition prevents
her conscious
exercise
of the choice.'"
In re Grady,
85 N.J. 235,
250, 426 A.2d
467,
474 (1981) (quoting
In re Quinlan,
70 N.J.
10, 41, 355 A.2d
647, 664,
cert. denied, 429
U.S. 922
(1976)).
26. See E. SCHULMAN,
FOCUS
ON THE
RETARDED
ADULT: PROGRAMS
AND
SERVICES 34-94
(1980).
Schulman
traces the
historical development
of conceptions
of
mental disability
and corre-
sponding
public policy responses.
The medical
model of retardation
dominated in the
late nineteenth
and early
twentieth
centuries. This
model described
and classified
several
organic causes
of
retardation
including
brain injury and
chromosomal
and genetic
abnormalities
such as Down's
Syndrome,
Tay
Sachs disease,
microcephaly,
and hydrocephaly.
The
medical approach
is useful
in un-
derstanding severe
retardation; persons
with Wechsler
IQs below 39 are
almost always in the
organically
impaired
category. See
R. MACKLIN
& W. GAYLIN,
MENTAL
RETARDATION
AND
STERILIZATION
13-14
(1981). But
organic pathology
does not
explain the
causes of disability
in
most mildly
retarded
persons; only
25% of mildly
retarded persons
are organically
impaired.
The
remaining 75%
may simply be comprised
of individuals
whose intelligence level
is at the lower end
of a continuum.
See E. SCHULMAN,
supra,
at 55. But
see B. MARTIN,
supra note
16, at 570-74
(describing
the extent
to which mild
retardation
has organic causes).
Professor
Zigler and others
developed the
cognitive developmental
approach that
applies
Piaget's
theories
to the functioning
of mentally
retarded
persons. See
Zigler, Mental
Retardation:
Current Issues
and Approaches,
2 REV. CHILD
DEV. RES.
107, 111-13
(1966). Piaget
postulated
that
human
intelligence
developed
in a series of
adaptive stages
occurring in
childhood and
adolescence.
See H. KAPLAN
& B. SADOCK,
MODERN
SYNOPSIS OF
COMPREHENSIVE
TEXTBOOK
OF PSYCHIATRY
57 (3d ed.
1981). Disabled
persons
progress through
the developmental
stages
at a slower
rate
than
normal children
and fail
to attain the
higher developmental
stages.
The stage
of cognitive
development
attained correlates
with the
level of mental retardation.
See id.
at 852.
27. A retarded person
is classified by
comparing her behavior
to a particular age
group's behavior
using
factors such
as academic
skill, social
responsiveness,
responsibility,
and vocational
per-
formance.
The classification
may change
as the retarded
person
develops or as
society's expectations
change. See H. KAPLAN
& B. SADOCK,
supra note 26, at 853.
Four commonly
used classifications
of mental
retardation have
been recognized by
the American Psychiatric
Association's Diagnostic
and Statistic
Manual of
Mental Disorders.
See id.
at 851. These
classifications
are based
on the
Weschler Intelligence
Quotient
of the affected
person. The four
classifications are:
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
Custodial programs that segregate and warehouse retarded persons
are no longer endorsed by professionals. Today, programs for mentally
retarded persons pursue the goal of "normalization'-the development
of skills that enable the individual to live as independently and self-sufficiently
as possible.
28
Issues of sexual autonomy are an important aspect
(1) Mild-IQ 51 to 70. Mildly retarded individuals can usually master basic academic skills.
Adults are capable of living independently or semi-independently in the community. See id. at 852.
Mildly retarded persons may need slight assistance such as health care reminders or help in purchasing
clothes. They are coordinated, can navigate their neighborhood, can communicate and under-
stand complex verbal concepts, and can perform semi-skilled or low skill jobs. See H. GROSSMAN,
CLASSIFICATION
IN MENTAL RETARDATION
(1983). Mildly retarded individuals handle
sexual impulses
and urges normally and can develop appropriate adaptive skills through education. See R.
MONAT, SEXUALITY AND THE MENTALLY RETARDED 6 (1982).
(2) Moderate-IQ 36 to 50. Many individuals functioning at this level can learn self-help,
communication, social, and simple occupational skills, but only limited academic or vocational
skills. See H. KAPLAN & B. SADOCK, supra note 26, at 852. Moderately retarded persons perform
personal hygiene tasks, possess gross and fine motor coordination, use complex sentences, and read
simple prose material; they may initiate activities and conscientiously perform simple household
tasks. See id. Moderately retarded persons can learn sexual responsibility, but self-experimentation
is common. See R. MONAT, supra, at 15.
(3) Severe-IQ 20 to 35. Severely retarded persons require continuing and close supervision,
but may perform self-help and simple work tasks. See H. KAPLAN & B. SADOCK, supra note 26, at
851-52. They can usually prepare simple foods and perform uncomplicated household tasks. Severely
retarded persons may use sentences and understand verbal communication, but they profit
most from systematic habit training. See id. They do not control sexual impulses well but conditioning
can alter their behavior to some extent. There is a limited ability to predict or foresee the
consequences of their sexual behavior. See R. MONAT, supra, at 3-4.
(4) Profound-IQ 0 to 20. Profoundly retarded persons require continuing and close supervi-
sion, but some may be able to perform simple self-help tasks. They often have handicaps and require
total life-support systems. See H. KAPLAN & B. SADOCK, supra note 26, at 851-52. Profoundly
retarded persons do not perform all personal hygiene tasks and generally use only simple language.
See id. Their sexual reactions are predominantly impulsive, they cannot easily engage in sexual
activity on a reciprocal level, and they often masturbate in a harmful or excessive way. See R.
MONAT, supra, at 4, 24-25.
28. Professor Nine is the leading proponent of normalization. He defined the concept as "making
available to the mentally subnormal patterns and conditions of everyday life which are as close as
possible to the norms and patterns of the mainstream of society." Nije, Symposium on "Normalization'"
The Normalization
Principle-Implications and Comments,
16 BRIT. J. MENTAL SUBNOR-
MALITY 62, 62 (1970). See also Wolfensburger, The Principle of Normalization and Its Implication to
Psychiatric Services, 127 AM. J. PSYCHIATRY 291, 291-97 (1970). Normalization has become the
primary objective of programs for the retarded.
The two central components
of normalization are deinstitutionalization
and educational main-
streaming. Experts generally agree that mentally retarded persons attain fuller development in community
settings
rather than in
institutions. Retarded children develop
better when they live with
their families and are reared
by their parents. Adults may also thrive
in a well-functioning family;
however, a residence for retarded adults may alternatively provide companionship and support. See
E. SCHULMAN, supra note 26, at 256-83.
The normalization approach also emphasizes educational mainstreaming. The federal law dealing
with the education of handicapped individuals supports this normalization principle. See 20
U.S.C. § 1412(5)
(1982) (state must provide "procedures
to assure that, to the maximum extent
appropriate, handicapped children ... are educated with children who are not handicapped").
816
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
[Vol.
1986:806
of
the
normalization
trend;
29
freedom
and
privacy
in social
and
sexual
relationships
may
be as
important
to mentally
disabled
persons
as
to
others.
Furthermore,
marriage
and
parenthood
are
realistic
options
for
some
mildly
disabled
persons
who,
with
appropriate
training,
may
be ca-
pable
of fulfilling
those
roles.
30
Sterilization
is
viewed
as rarely
desirable
because
many
mentally
retarded
persons
are presumed
to have
at
least
a
potential
interest
in having
children.
Many
mildly
retarded
persons have
been "mainstreamed"
into
regular classrooms.
See E. SCHULMAN,
supra
note
26,
at 65.
Implicit
in the concept
of normalization
is the
notion that
mentally retarded
persons
should
enjoy
the same legal
rights
as others
to the extent
that they
are able to
do so. In
an official
statement
in
1973, the
American
Academy
of Mental
Deficiency
emphasized
that
"[m]entally
retarded
citizens
are entitled
to enjoy
and exercise
the
same rights
as
are available
to
nonretarded
citizens,
to
the
limits
of their ability
to do so."
Rights of Mentally
Retarded
Persons:
An Official Statement
of the
American
Academy of Mental
Deficiency,
MENTAL
RETARDATION,
Oct. 1973, at
56, 56-57. See
also
Wald,
Basic Personal
and Civil
Rights, in THE
PRESIDENT'S
COMMITTEE
ON MENTAL
RETARDATION,
THE MENTALLY
RETARDED
CITIZEN
AND THE LAW
3 (1976).
Some commentators
argue
that zealous
commitment
to the principle
of normalization
in
education
may
not help
seriously impaired
persons
because
the quality
of
the individual's
educational
experience
depends on
factors other
than
physical placement.
See, e.g.,
Vitello, Cautions
on
the
Road to
Normalization,
MENTAL RETARDATION,
Oct.
1974, at 39,
40.
29. The notion
that mentally
disabled
persons are sexual
beings is
only recently
gaining acceptance
among
professionals
who
work
with
this
population.
In
the
past,
dealing
with
sexual
behavior
was
viewed as
a "problem";
usually, preventing
sexual contact
among
residents or
participants in
programs/placements
for mentally
retarded
persons was
standard policy.
Mentally
retarded persons
have traditionally
been deemed
incapable
of controlling
sexual
impulses,
a view
that is clearly
erro-
neous as applied
to mildly
retarded persons.
See E. SCHULMAN,
supra
note 26, at
298. Today,
as
part
of the normalization
trend,
sex education
is an important
part of
programs for
mentally re-
tarded
persons. Helping
the individual
deal with
sexual issues
in a positive and
socially appropriate
manner
has become
the objective
of many
programs.
See S.
HAARIK
& K. MENNINGER,
SEXUALITY,
LAW,
AND
THE DEVELOPMENTALLY
DISABLED PERSON
151 (1981);
R. MONAT,
supra note
27,
at 46-49; E.
SCHULMAN,
supra note
26, at 292-312.
30.
Historically,
many states have
statutorily
prohibited
or restricted
marriage by mentally
retarded
persons.
See
Note,
The
Right
of
the
Mentally
Disabled
to
Marry:
A
Statutory
Evaluation,
15
J.
FAM.
L. 463, 487-507
(1977). States
have begun
to repeal
these statutes
because of a
growing
awareness that
some mentally
retarded persons
may successfully
marry
and rear children.
See Shaman,
Persons
Who
Are
Mentally
Retarded:
Their
Right
to
Marry
and
Have
Children,
12
FAM.
L.Q.
61, 84
(1978); Note,
Retarded Parents
in Neglect
Proceedings:
The Erroneous
Assumption
of Parental
Inadequacy,
31 STAN.
L. REV. 785,
804 (1979).
Mental
retardation
professionals
generally support
normalization;
however,
many are
still concerned
about
the
capability
of mentally
retarded
persons
to be
parents.
Indeed, one
goal among
professionals
has been to promote
normal
relationships
that are not
burdened by
the possibility
of
pregnancy.
See E. SCHULMAN,
supra note
26, at 301-03.
There
is growing
recognition,
however,
that
some mentally
disabled persons
can function
as parents.
See Rosenberg
& McTate,
Intellectu-
ally Handicapped
Mothers:
Problems
and Perspectives,
CHILDREN
TODAY,
Jan.-Feb. 1982,
at 24.
Authorities seem
to require
that mentally
retarded parents
provide
a higher standard
of care than
that
generally expected
of normal
parents.
See Murphy,
Coleman & Abel,
Human Sexuality
it the
Mentally Retarded,
in TREATMENT
ISSUES
AND INNOVATIONS
IN MENTAL
RETARDATION
614
(J.
Matson & F.
Andrasik eds.
1983). Recently
there has
been a focus on
supportive services
and training
in
parenting
skills for
mentally retarded
persons.
See Madsen,
Parenting Classes
for the Mentally
Retarded,
17 MENTAL
RETARDATION
195, 195 (1979);
Rosenberg
& McTate,
supra, at 24.
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
B. Current Sterilization Law.
The preceding factors
have stimulated the reform
of sterilization law
in recent
years. A few jurisdictions
have banned sterilization of incompe-
tent persons altogether.
31
Under most reform laws, however, the state
may authorize
sterilization under its parens
patriae authority if certain
conditions
are met.
32
Many of these laws
follow a model derived from
a
Washington
Supreme Court case,
In re Guardianship of Hayes.
Hayes
requires a two-part
inquiry. First, the court must
determine whether the
individual is competent
to make an informed medical
decision about sterilization.
34
This inquiry seeks
to protect the autonomy
interest of the
31.
See COLO. REv. STAT. § 27-10.5-128(2)
(Supp. 1985) ("No person with developmental
disabilities
who
has not given consent shall be
sterilized."). In 1981, the Colorado Supreme
Court
carved out an exception to allow sterilization of mentally retarded minors. See In re A.W., 637 P.2d
366, 375 (Colo. 1981).
A California law prohibiting sterilization
of all persons under conservator-
ship, CAL. PROB. CODE § 2356 (1981), was struck down in 1985 in Conservatorship of Valerie N.,
40 Cal. 3d 143, 160-61, 707 P.2d 760, 771-72, 219 Cal. Rptr. 387, 398-99 (1985). Several courts have
effectively
banned sterilization by refusing to allow
sterilization in the absence of statutory
authority.
See infra note 32. Federal law prohibits government funding of the sterilization of minors and
incompetents. See ReIf v. Weinberger,
372 F. Supp. 1196, 1201 (D.D.C. 1974)
(Secretary of HEW
has no
authority to fund sterilization of minors
or mentally incompetent persons who are
incompetent
to consent to the operation); 42 C.F.R. § 50.207 (1985) (prohibiting federally assisted family-
planning projects from
funding hysterectomies performed solely
for the purpose of sterilization).
32. During the 1960's and 1970's, many states repealed eugenic sterilization laws, often without
making
alternative provisions for sterilization of
incompetents. Courts generally rejected
petitions to
obtain sterilization of mentally retarded persons because of the absence of statutory authority. See
Wade v. Bethesda Hosp., 337 F. Supp. 671, 673-74 (S.D. Ohio 1971); Hudson v. Hudson, 373 So. 2d
310, 312 (Ala. 1979);
Guardianship of Kemp, 43 Cal. App. 3d
758, 761-62, 118 Cal. Rptr. 64, 66-67
(1974); A.L. v. G.R.H., 163 Ind. App. 636, 638, 325 N.E.2d 501, 502 (1975), cerL denied, 425 U.S.
936 (1976); Holmes v.
Powers, 439 S.W.2d 579, 580 (Ky. Ct. App.
1968); In re M.K.R., 515 S.W.2d
467, 470 (Mo. 1974);
Frazier v. Levi, 440 S.W.2d 393, 394 (Tex.
Civ. App. 1969). But see In re
Sallmaier, 85 Misc. 2d 295, 297-98,
378 N.Y.S.2d 989, 991 (Sup. Ct. 1976);
In re Simpson, 180
N.E.2d 206, 208
(Ohio P. Ct.
1962).
In 1978, the United States Supreme Court held that judicial immunity protected an Indiana
judge who had authorized
the sterilization of a young woman
in the absence of statutory authority.
Stump v. Sparkman, 435 U.S. 349, 356 (1978). Immunity applied because the judge's decision was
not in the "clear absence of all jurisdiction,"
although the judge may have erred
or exceeded his
authority. Id. at 356-57.
Although Stump does not directly
affirm judicial authority, it opened the
path for a series of
decisions recognizing
the parens patriae power to order the sterilization
of mentally disabled persons
in the absence of statutory authority.
Several states have enacted statutory provisions that sanction parens patriae sterilization of
incompetents. See statutes cited supra note 3. Most recent laws are grounded in the state's parens
patriae authority; earlier laws, in
contrast, were usually based on
the police power.
33. 93 Wash. 2d 228, 608 P.2d 635 (1980).
34. The Hayes court explained that:
[T]he judge must first find by clear, cogent and convincing evidence that the individual is
(1) incapable of making his or her
own decision about sterilization, and
(2) unlikely to
develop sufficiently to make an informed
judgment about sterilization
in the foreseeable
future.
Id. at 238, 608 P.2d at 641.
3
3
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
If
the court determines that the
person is incompetent, it must
then consider
specific factors and decide
whether sterilization is
in the person's
competent person who has no need for a surrogate decisionmaker.
best
interest.
3
6
Most laws following
the Hayes
decision
embody strict
procedural
and
substantive requirements that
create a strong presumption
against
sterilization. These
laws presume that there
is a conflict of interest between
the
child and
the parent in this
context and
consequently
exclude
parents
from any role
in the decision.
37
decision in a formal "semi-adversarial"
proceeding.
[Vol. 1986:806
A court
makes the sterilization
3 8
35
The
retarded indi-
35.
Some states folow Hayes and require a
threshold determination of the person's
competency
to make
the sterilization decision before considering
whether nonconsensual sterilization
is appropri-
ate. See In re C.D.M.,
627 P.2d 607, 612
(Alaska 1981); Wentzel
v. Montgomery
Gen. Hosp., Inc.,
293
Md. 685, 702, 447 A.2d 1244, 1253 (1982),
cerL denied, 459 U.S. 1147 (1983); In
re Moe, 385
Mass. 555, 566, 432 N.E.2d
712, 721 (1982); In re Grady, 85 N.J. 235,
264, 426 A.2d 467, 483
(1981); In re Terwilliger,
304 Pa. Super.
553, 565, 450 A.2d
1376, 1383 (1982); COLO.
REV. STAT.
§ 27-10.5-130
(Supp. 1985); CONN. GEN. STAT.
ANN. § 45-788 (West 1981); ME. REV.
STAT. ANN.
tit. 34-B,
§ 7005 (Supp. 1986);
OR. REV. STAT.
§ 436.225(3) (1985);
UTAH CODE ANN.
§ 64-10-2
(1986); VT. STAT. ANN.
tit. 18, § 8707
(Supp. 1986); VA. CODE
ANN. § 54-325.9
(1982). Although
many
laws state that the first
determination is incompetency,
only a
few clearly stop the
inquiry if
competency is found. See CONN.
GEN. STAT. ANN. § 45-78W (West 1981);
ME. REV. STAT. ANN.
tit. 34-B,
§ 7008 (1986). A
few states permit sterilization
on a general
finding of incompetency.
See
In re Penny N., 120 N.H. 269,
271, 414 A.2d 541, 543 (1980) ("The court
must [find] that the ward
is 'incapacitated'..
. and
suffers a 'developmental
disability'.....);
MINN. STAT. ANN.
§ 252
A.11-13
(West 1982)
(conservatee may
be sterilized upon
best interest
finding).
36.
See Hayes, 93 Wash.
2d at 237, 608 P.2d
at 640.
37. The parent's
petition generally
triggers the appointment
of a guardian
ad litem to represent
the child's
interests. See Grady, 85 N.J. at 252,
426 A.2d at 475 (incompetents are best
protected by
independent judicial
decisionmaking,
not parents' good
faith decision); Hayes,
93 Wash. 2d at 236,
608 P.2d at 640
(parents' interests
cannot be presumed
to be identical
to those of child).
Some
laws characterize the court's role as deciding
whether to authorize the parent/guardian
to
consent to sterilization;
however, this
does not signify
any abdication to parental
decisionmaking
authority in terms
of relaxed procedural
or substantive
standards. See, e.g.,
Wenizel, 293 Md.
at
701, 447 A.2d at 1254
(guardian's decision authorized only if
sterilization is medically necessary).
38.
See C.D.M., 627
P.2d at 612 (procedural
due process requires
full judicial
hearing with
medical testimony and
guardian ad litem to represent incompetent);
Grady, 85 N.J. at 252, 426 A.2d
at 475 (independent judicial decisionmaking
best protects interests of incompetents).
Most laws
specify a range
of procedural protections
such as representation
by counsel and
expert evaluation of
the retarded person. See Wenizel, 293
Md. at 703, 447 A.2d at 1253 (independent
medical, psychological,
and
social
evaluations
by competent
professionals); Hayes,
93 Wash. 2d at 238,
608 P.2d at
641
(comprehensive medical,
psychological,
and social evaluation);
COLO. REV. STAT.
§ 27-10-5130(1)
(Supp.
1985) (appointment of two mental health
professionals to perform evaluations); CONN.
GEN.
STAT. ANN. § 45-78t
(West 1981) (appointment
of counsel);
IDAHO CODE §
39-3903(a),(d)
(1985)
(appointment of
two physicians); ME.
REV. STAT. ANN.
tit. 34-B, § 7008.2
(Supp. 1986)
(appointment
of not
less than two disinterested
mental health
experts); MINN.
STAT. ANN.
§ 252A.13.4 (West 1982) (appointment
of counsel and written medical, social,
and psychological
evaluations);
UTAH CODE
ANN. § 64-10-8(2)
(1986) (appointment
of counsel); VT. STAT.
ANN. tit.
18, § 8710 (Supp. 1986) (appointment
of counsel); VA. CODE ANN. § 54-325.12.B
(1982) (independent
medical, social, and psychological evaluations).
Some laws accord other procedural
protections such as notice of the
proceedings, the right to
cross-examine witnesses, and the right
to pursue an appeal. See Moe, 385 Mass.
at 566-67, 432
Vol. 1986:806] STERILIZATION
vidual
is represented
by an attorney,
usually a
guardian ad litem,
who
Most
of the reform
laws allow a
court to order
sterilization only
upon findings
may
be
directed
to
oppose
the
parents'
petition
for
sterilization.
based on
clear and convincing
evidence.
4
In addition
to procedural
restrictions,
these laws
employ rigorous
substantive
criteria to
guide the court's
deliberations.
Some require
inquiries
into
whether
the
individual
is
able
to
reproduce
41
39
and whether she
N.E.2d
at 721 (adequate notice, opportunity to
be heard, and pursuit of appeal); Grady,
85 N.J. at
264, 426
A.2d at 482 (appointment
of guardian ad
litem and opportunity
to present proofs
and cross-
examine);
Terwilliger, 304 Pa.
Super. at 565, 450
A.2d at 1383 (same);
COLO. REV. STAT.
§ 27-10.5129(2),
(3)
(1982) (notice, presence
at proceeding,
and opportunity to
cross-examine); CONN.
GEN.
STAT.
ANN. §§ 45-78s to 78y(a) (West Supp.
1986) (notice, opportunity to testify and
cross-examine);
ME.
REV. STAT. ANN.
tit. 34-B, §§ 7007.3,
7008.1 (Supp.
1986) (opportunity
to present
evidence, call witnesses,
and cross-examine); OR. REV. STAT.
§§ 436.255(2), 436.275(2), 436.315
(1983) (appointment
of counsel on
appeal and opportunity
to present evidence
and cross-examine
witnesses);
VT. STAT. ANN.
tit. 18, §§ 8709(c), 8711,
8714 (Supp. 1986)
(notice and right to
appeal);
VA. CODE ANN. §
54-325.11.2 (1982) (notice of proceedings
and appointment of counsel).
39.
See, eg., Moe, 385 Mass.
at 567, 432 N.E.2d
at 721.
40. In In re A.W., 637 P.2d 366, 373-75
(Colo. 1981), the Colorado Supreme
Court interpreted
COLO. REV. STAT. §
15-14-312 (Supp. 1986) to allow court-ordered
sterilization upon a showing of
clear and convincing
evidence.
The law of Maine
specifically requires
"clear and convincing
evidence
that
sterilization
is in the best
interest of the person
being considered
for sterilization." ME.
REV. STAT.
ANN. tit. 34-B, § 7013(4)
(Supp. 1986).
In Wentzel v. Montgomery
Gen. Hosp.,
Inc.,
293
Md. 685, 447 A.2d
1244 (1982), cert
denied, 459 U.S. 1147
(1983), the Maryland
Supreme
Court held that
section 13-702 of the
Maryland Estates
and Trusts Code empowered
the court
to
adopt standards
that would ensure
the ward's best
interest regarding proposed
sterilization.
The
New Hampshire
Supreme Court
ruled that under a
statute mandating court
approval of guardian-
requested
sterilization,
N.H. REv. STAT. ANN.
§ 464-A:25I(e)
(1983), the guardian
must present
clear and convincing
proof that the ward
is incapacitated, and
that the guardian is
acting in the best
interest of the ward.
In re Penny N., 120
N.H. 269, 271-72,
414 A.2d 541, 543 (1980).
The proponent
of a sterilization in New Jersey must
show by clear and convincing evidence
that the person to
be sterilized lacks the
capacity to consent
or withhold consent.
See Grady, 85 N.J.
at 265, 426 A.2d
at
483. The Pennsylvania
Supreme Court
required "proof by clear
and convincing
evidence that
sterilization is
in the best interest of the incompetent."
Terwilliger, 304 Pa. Super. at 564, 450 A.2d
at 1382. Virginia statutory law
requires a court to determine "by clear
and convincing evidence"
that a child
is incapable of making
a decision before
that court can order
sterilization. VA.
CODE
ANN. § 54-325.10 (1982). In
order for any incompetent in Virginia to
be sterilized, the statutory
elements must be shown by
clear and convincing evidence. VA. CODE
ANN. § 54-325.12 (1982).
The Washington
Supreme Court
stated that the
requirements for a court-ordered
sterilization
must
be proven by "clear, cogent and
convincing evidence." Hayes, 93 Wash.
2d at 238-39, 608 P.2d at
641.
41. See In re C.D.M.,
627 P.2d 607, 613
(Alaska 1981) ("[I]t
must then be established
that the
incompetent is capable
of reproduction
.... "); Terwilliger, 304
Pa. Super. at 566,
450 A.2d at 1383
("[T]he
person for whom sterilization is requested
must be proven capable of reproduction.");
Hayes,
93 Wash. 2d at 238,
608 P.2d at 641 ("The
judge must find that
the individual is...
physically
capable
of conceiving
.... ); CONN. GEN.
STAT. ANN. § 45-78p(d)
(West Supp. 1986)
("no
evidence
of infertility"); ME. REV. STAT. ANN.
tit. 34-B, § 7011 (West Supp. 1986)
(petition for
sterilization must
include a "medical
statement assessing
the physiological capability
of the person
to
procreate");
N.C. GEN. STAT.
§ 635-39 (1984)
(petition for involuntary
sterilization must
state
whether
patient is likely
to procreate).
Some
courts seem to presume
reproductive
capacity from the
existence of regular
monthly periods
and
the
absence of contrary
medical evidence. See
Grady. 85 N.J. at
266, 426 A.2d at 483;
In re
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
is "imminently" likely to engage in sexual activity.
42
The petitioner will
be asked to demonstrate that less drastic forms of contraception have
been tried and are not feasible.
ual's capacity to care for a
child.
43
The court must also assess the individ-
44
Some states require a
determination
that sterilization is medically essential to preserve the life or the physical
or mental health of the individual.
45
In some states, the court must also
inquire into the disabled person's understanding of reproductive functions
and the relationship between sexual intercourse, pregnancy, and
childbirth.
46
Some laws direct the court to consider the psychological
trauma associated with sterilization and alternatively with pregnancy
Truesdell, 63 N.C. App. 258,
283, 304 S.E.2d 793, 808 (1983), aff'd as
modified, 313 N.C. 421, 329
S.E.2d 630 (1985). Other courts require further affirmative medical proof. See In re Debra B., 495
A.2d 781, 783 (Me. 1985) (mother's sterilization petition denied because she failed to present clear
and convincing evidence to prove that 26 year-old daughter was capable of procreation). Such re-
quirements may involve an intrusive medical examination to prove reproductive capacity (or postponing
the sterilization initiative until the person has become pregnant).
42.
See Moe, 385 Mass. at 570, 432 N.E.2d
at 722; Terwilliger, 304 Pa. Super. at 567,
450 A.2d
at 1384; Hayes, 93 Wash. 2d at 238, 608 P.2d at 641; CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 45-78p(d)(4) (West
Supp. 1986); UTAH CODE ANN. § 64-10-8(1)(d) (1983); VT. STAT. ANN. tit. 18, § 8711(c)(3)(B)
(Supp. 1986); VA. CODE ANN. § 54-325.12.A.1 (1982). But see Grady, 85 N.J. at 266, 426 A.2d at
483 (no need to show likelihood of pregnancy).
43. Many laws require that all less drastic (nonpermanent) contraceptive methods be unwork-
able and that there be no alternative to sterilization. See C.D.M., 627 P.2d at 613; In re A.W., 637
P.2d 366, 376 (Colo. 1981); Moe, 385 Mass. at 569, 432 N.E.2d at 722; Grady, 85 N.J. at 266, 426
A.2d at 483; Hayes, 93 Wash. 2d at 237, 608 P.2d at 640; CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 45-78p(d)(1)
(West Supp. 1986); GA. CODE ANN. § 31-20-3(c)(2) (1985); ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 34-B,
§7013(5)(a) (Supp. 1984); MINN. STAT. §252A.13.4 (1982); VT. STAT. ANN. tit. 18,
§ 8711(a)(3)(E) (Supp.
1986); VA. CODE § 54-325.12.A.2 (1982);
W. VA. CODE § 27-16-1 (1980).
44. See CD.M., 627 P.2d at 613; Moe, 385 Mass. at 569, 432 N.E.2d at 722; Grady, 85 N.J. at
266, 426 A.2d at 483; Terwilliger, 304 Pa. Super. at 567, 450 A.2d at 1384; Hayes, 93 Wash. 2d at
238, 608 P.2d at 641; CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 45-78p(d)(6) (West Supp. 1983); OR. REV. STAT.
§ 436.205(e); VT. STAT. ANN. tit. 18, § 871 1(c)(3)(C) (Supp. 1986); VA. CODE ANN. § 54325.12.A.4
(1982); W. VA. CODE § 27-16-1(3) (1980).
45. See A. W., 637 P.2d at 375; Moe, 385 Mass. at 569 n.10, 432 N.E.2d at 722 n.10; CONN.
GEN. STAT. ANN. § 45-78p(d)(8) (West Supp. 1983); ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 34-B, § 7013.5
(Supp. 1984). Colorado requires this
finding to protect the individual's health
and "fundamental
procreative rights." A. W., 637 P.2d at 376. Courts in Maryland must make a finding of medical
necessity and also determine whether sterilization is in the individual's best interest. See Wentzel V.
Montgomery Gen. Hosp., Inc., 293 Md. 685, 703, 447 A.2d 1244, 1253-54 (1982), cert. denied, 459
U.S. 1147 (1983).
In Conservatorship of Valerie N., 40 Cal. 3d 143, 169, 707 P.2d 760, 777, 219 Cal. Rptr. 387,
404 (1985), the California Supreme Court seemed to require medical necessity because of the absence
of a statute. The court directed, pending legislative action, that the procedures for approving intru-
sive medical procedures for conservatees be applied to sterilization.
In general,
the "medical necessity" requirement treats
sterilization like other medical proce-
dures for incompetents. However, sterilization is also a reproductive option which normal persons
choose for reasons other than health promotion. The New Jersey Supreme Court has rejected a
required showing of "medical necessity" as too restrictive of the rights of the retarded person. See
Grady. 85 N.J. at 262-63, 426 A.2d at 481.
46. See Grady, 85 N.J. at 266, 426 A.2d at 483; Terwilliger, 304 Pa. Super. at 567, 450 A.2d at
Vol.
1986:806]
STERILIZATION
and
childbirth.
47
Additionally,
an
inquiry
into the individual's
prefer-
ences
about sterilization
may be
required, although
her
objection
is not
determinative.
48
The
Hayes
decision and
some later
laws require
findings
that medical
science
is not
on the verge
of breakthroughs
that will
correct
the
individual's
disability
or
make
reversible
sterilization
available.
These
various
criteria create
formidable
substantive
barriers
to the
sterili-
zation
of
mentally
retarded
persons.
5 0
Current
law explicitly
or implicitly
excludes some
variables from
the
court's
consideration,
such
as the
state's interest
in protecting
society
from
the genetic
and
financial burden
of
children produced
by
retarded
persons.
51
The parents'
interest
in protecting
their
child from
unwanted
47. See Grady,
85 N.J.
at 266, 426
A.2d at 483; Terwilliger,
304
Pa. Super.
at 567, 450 A.2d
at
1384; Hayes,
93 Wash. 2d at
238-39, 608
P.2d at 641-42;
ME. REV. STAT.
ANN. tit.
34-B, § 7013.3.B
(Supp.
1986); OR. REV.
STAT. § 436.205(1) (1985).
48.
Several laws
specify that
the retarded
person has
a right to be
present at the
hearing and
further direct
the court
to inquire about
the person's
wishes and gain
impressions
about her compe-
tency.
See CD.M.,
627 P.2d at
613 n.17 (weight
given the individual's
preferences
varies
according
to ability
to comprehend);
A. W., 637
P.2d at 375
(person's wish
not to be sterilized
weighs
heavily
against
authorizing
the procedure);
Wentzel,
293 Md. at
703, 447 A.2d
at 1253 (court
must allow
full opportunity
for individual
to express
views); Grady,
85 N.J. at
265, 426 A.2d
at 482 (same);
Terwilliger,
304 Pa. Super.
at 565-66,
450 A.2d
at 1383 (judge
must meet with
individual,
but not
necessarily
at hearing);
Hayes, 93
Wash. 2d at 238,
608 P.2d
at 641 (court
must elicit individual's
views before
ordering sterilization);
ME.
REv. STAT.
ANN. tit. 34-B,
§ 7011.9
(Supp. 1986)
(court
must consider
the person's
attitudes
or desires regarding
sterilization
before
sanctioning the
procedure);
UTAH
CODE ANN.
§ 64-10-8(3)
(1986) (record
must include
the person's
views on issue
of
sterilization);
VA.
CODE ANN.
§ 54-325.11.5
(1982)
(court
must elicit
and thoroughly
consider
the
child's
views on
sterilization).
49. See Moe,
385 Mass.
at 570, 432 N.E.2d
at 722;
Grady, 85
N.J. at 266, 426
A.2d at 483;
Terwilliger,
304
Pa. Super. at
567, 450 A.2d
at 1384; IDAHO
CODE § 39-3901(e)
(1985);
UTAH CODE
ANN. § 64-10-8(1)(a)
(1986);
VT. STAT.
ANN. tit. 18,
§ 8711 (c)(3)(D)
(Supp. 1986);
VA. CODE
ANN.
§ 54-325.11.4
(1982).
50. Indeed,
this is the intention.
Several courts
state clearly that sterilization
of an incompetent
is seldom
in her best interest.
For example,
the Washington
Supreme
Court has
stated that
there is a
"heavy presumption
against
sterilization
... that must
be overcome
by the person
... requesting
sterilization."
Hayes, 93
Wash. 2d at
239, 608 P.2d
at 641. See
also C.D.M.,
627 P.2d at
612
(advocates
of sterilization
bear heavy
burden of proving
that sterilization
is in
the incompetent's
best
interest).
It is interesting
to note
the similarity
between
the procedural
and substantive
requirements
of
the recent parens
patriae laws
and the remaining
police-power
laws.
Compare statutes
cited supra
note 3
with GA. CODE
ANN. § 31-20-3(a)
(1985);
IDAHO CODE
§ 39-3901(a)
(1985); N.C.
GEN.
STAT. §
35-39(3)
(1984).
The police-power
laws require
these protections
because
sterilization
is viewed
as a deprivation
of
the fundamental
right to procreate.
It is
clear that parens
patriae laws
are grounded
in the same
notion. Thus,
despite rhetoric
about the
exercise of reproductive
choice,
see Grady,
85 N.J. at 24751,
426
A.2d
at
473-74, reform
laws treat sterilization
as
an infringement
on the person's
rights just
as do the
police-power
laws.
51.
See Grady,
85 N.J. at 262
n.8, 426 A.2d
at 481 n.8
(court should
consider
"only the best
interests
of the
incompetent
person,
not the interests
or
convenience
of society").
Grady
rejected
the
use
of sterilization
to promote
genetic objectives
or to prevent
the birth
of children who
would be
a
burden
to society.
The Colorado
Supreme
Court
has stated
that sterilization
is to be allowed
only
if
4 9
DUKE
LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
pregnancy or in avoiding
the inconvenience associated
with menstrual
hygiene is also excluded from
consideration.
52
Finally, the
disabled individual's
interest in promoting family stability by reducing the stress asso-
ciated with her care may not be considered.
The substantive criteria that guide the decisionmaker are formulated
into
four kinds of legal rules. The
Hayes opinion adopts the most
com-
mon approach,
which could be termed
a "mandatory criteria" rule;
under
this type of rule a court can
authorize sterilization only
if several
specific findings are clearly made.
53
This rule places a significant burden
on the petitioner,
limits judicial discretion, and
makes it difficult to estab-
lish
the desirability of sterilization.
The "discretionary best
interest"
standard is a more flexible rule; instead of requiring specific findings, it
directs judges to consider
and weigh designated criteria
in determining
whether sterilization is in the
incompetent person's best interest.
"medically
essential"
and
has
emphasized
that
only
the
interests
of
the
person
herself,
and
not
those
of society or her parents, are to be considered. A. W., 637 P.2d at 376. See also Terwilliger, 304 Pa.
Super. at 564, 450 A.2d at 1382 ("[A] court should consider only the interests of the individual
52. Some laws require
parents to demonstrate their good faith
and concern for their child's best
interest. See GD.M.,
627 P.2d at 613 (court must examine motivation
behind petition); Wentzel,
293 Md. at 704-05, 447
A.2d at 1254 ("[IThe welfare of society
or the convenience or peace of mind
of the ward's parents or guardian plays no part."); In re Penny N., 120 N.H. 269, 271, 414 A.2d 541,
543
(1980) ("["]he court must be satisfied that...
the applicants have demonstrated their
good faith
and that their concern is for the best interests of the ward."); CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 4578p(d)(7)
(West
Supp. 1986) (applicants'
"primary concern" must be best interest
of the
incompetent).
53. See Hayes, 93 Wash. 2d at 238-39,
608 P.2d at 641. This kind of law in
effect restricts the
discretion
of the judge; the legislature or appellate
court designating the criteria determines
the
sterilization
decision. As a legal decision principle,
it may be easier to apply than the discretionary
best interest standard, see infra note 54, because it incorporates fewer factual variables. However,
the rule as applied may not result in decisions that benefit the individual for whom sterilization is
proposed.
Thus, costs of error are high. The
analysis in Parts II and III of this article suggests
that
this kind of rule may
offer the greatest risk of error. See generally
Ehrlich & Posner, An Economic
Analysis ofLegal Rulemaking,
3 J. LEGAL STUD. 257, 267-71 (1974) (discussing
correlation of costs
to variations
in precision of legal rules). For an
analysis of variations in types of decision
principles
in child custody law, see Scott & Derdeyn, Rethinking Joint Custody, 45 OHIO ST. L.J. 455 (1984).
54. See Penny N., 120 N.H. at 271, 414 A.2d at 543; Terwilliger, 304 Pa. Super. at 564-67, 450
A.2d
at 1383-84; CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN.
§ 45-78y(b) (West Supp. 1986); MINN.
STAT.
§ 252A.13.4 (1982); OR.
REV. STAT. § 436.305(l) (1985); VT.
STAT. ANN. tit. 18, § 8712(c) (Supp.
1986).
Even under the discretionary
best interest standard, most
laws require the court to make a
finding of whether the
individual is competent to make the sterilization
decision. If the individual is
incompetent, these laws require the court to consider several substantive criteria and decide whether
there is clear and convincing
evidence that sterilization is in the
person's best interest. Error under
this standard may occur if the court
fails accurately to weigh the various criteria
in the decision.
Maryland requires a finding of medical necessity but also directs the court to weigh several factors in
determining
whether sterilization is in the person's
best interest. Wentzel. 293 Md. at
702-03, 447
A.2d at 1253-54. Thus, a finding that sterilization is in the person's best interest would not suffice:
sterilization
must also be a medical necessity.
The requirement of a best-interest finding
seems su-
5 4
A few
Vol.
1986:806]
STERILIZATION
states have
adopted
the "substituted
judgment"
approach
first proposed
by the
New Jersey
Supreme
Court
in In re
Grady.
55
Grady
directs
the
court to
consider
the
Hayes
criteria
and any
other
relevant
factors
in
order
to make
the decision
that the
disabled
person
would
make
for herself
if
she
were
competent.
5
6
Finally,
a few jurisdictions
simply
prohibit
the
sterilization
of
anyone
found
by the
court to
be incompetent
to give
informed
consent
to
the
medical
procedureP
7
On
a functional
level,
the various
legal rules
seem
to promote
differ-
ent objectives.
A rule
prohibiting
sterilization
without
the
subject's
informed
consent
apparently
aims
to
protect
only the
right
to procreate.
Sterilization
is
by definition
a violation
of this
right,
regardless
of the
person's
preferences.
At the
other
extreme,
the substituted
judgment
standard
attempts,
at least
in theory,
to approximate
the
choice that
the
perfluous,
since a
procedure that
is medically
necessary would
arguably
always be in
the person's
best interest.
55. 85 NJ. 235,
426 A.2d 467
(1981).
56. Id. at
264-67, 426
A.2d at 482-83.
See also In
re Moe, 385
Mass. 555,
565-71, 432 N.E.2d
712,
720-23
(1982); UTAH
CODE
ANN. § 64-10-8(4)
(1986).
The
substituted
judgment
doctrine
has
frequently
been used
in cases involving
medical
decisions for
individuals who
have become
incompe-
tent. Many
of these
decisions
involve attempts
to
withdraw
life-sustaining
treatment
from terminally
ill patients.
The
landmark
case is In
re Quinlan,
70 N.J. 10,
355 A.2d
647, cert.
denied, 429
U.S. 922
(1976). The
New Jersey Supreme
Court
held that a
21 year-old woman
in a persistent
vegetative
state
had a
right, which
her father
as her appointed
guardian
could
exercise
on her
behalf, to withdrawal
of
life-sustaining
treatment.
Id.
at
41-42,
355
A.2d at
664. The objective
of the substituted
judgment
approach is
for the decisionmaker
to "step
into the shoes"
of the incompetent
in
order to
make a
decision that
subjectively
reflects
what the
individual's
values and
preferences
would
be were
she competent.
Id. In theory,
the decision
may reflect
subjective idiosyncratic
values
and need
not
be the one
that objectively
reflects the
person's best
interest.
Courts
have
applied the
substituted
judgment
approach
in cases
involving
individuals
who
have
never been
competent.
See Superintendent
of Belchertown
State
School v. Saikewicz,
373 Mass.
728,
750-51,
370 N.E.2d
417, 430
(1977) (chemotherapy
withheld
from profoundly
retarded
67
year-old
man).
The application
of
the substituted
judgment
approach
is problematic
because it
requires the
surrogate
decisionmaker
to discern
the competent
values and
preferences
of a never-competent
person.
By
establishing
objective
criteria
to aid in approximating
the disabled
person's
best
interest, the
cases applying
the substituted
judgment
approach
implicitly
recognize the
pitfalls of a subjective
inquiry.
See Grady,
85 N.J.
at 266-67,
426 A.2d
at 483
(determination
based
on a range
of factors,
including
incompetency).
In
this way,
despite the
rhetoric,
the substituted
judgment
approach
is
similar to
the discretionary
best
interest
approach.
The Wisconsin
Supreme
Court
accurately
characterized
the
effort
to reach
the sterilization
decision that
the incompetent
retarded person
would
make taking
into account
anything that
would have
been relevant
to her including
her incompetency
as "legal
legerdemain."
In re
Guardianship
of Eberhardy,
102
Wis. 2d
539, 566,
307 N.W.2d
881,
893 (1981).
A presidential
commission
recommended
that courts
apply an
objective best
interest standard
to surrogates'
decisions
to withdraw
life-sustaining
treatment
from
persons
who had
never been
competent,
although the
commission
endorsed the
substituted judgment
approach
for persons
who
had once
expressed competent
preferences.
PRESIDENT'S
COMM'N
FOR THE
STUDY OF ETHICAl.
PROBLEMS
IN
MEDICINE
AND BIOMEDICAL
AND BEHAVIORAL
RESEARCH,
SUBSTANTIVE
AND
PROCEDURAL
PRINCIPLES
OF DECISIONMAKING
FOR
INCAPACITATED
PATIENTS
179-88 (1983).
57. See
supra note
31.
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
individual
would make if she were
competent. Between these
two extremes
are
laws
that
attempt
to
protect
the
individual's
interest
in
procre-
ation
from parental or state interference.
5 8
Despite variation,
however,
the reform
laws are all based on a paternalism
model. The model pro-
tects the mentally disabled
person by establishing
a heavy presumption
against sterilization and by requiring a judicial decisionmaker.
C. The
Limits of Good Intentions:
Some Problems with the
Paternalism Model
The rigorously protective
approach of the paternalism
model may
seem to offer a desirable
level of protection when parents
propose sterilization.
The irreversibility
of the medical procedure
in itself justifies caution.
Given the abuses
of the past and lingering biases
toward mentally
retarded persons,
a rule that constrains
the surrogate decisionmaker by
a
strong
presumption against sterilization
would seem to be justified.
Some retarded persons,
however, may be hurt by
laws based on the
paternalism model because
that model places the interest
in procreation
above
all other interests, including
the interest in avoiding pregnancy.
Like other
people, a retarded person may
have an interest in engaging
in
a sexual
relationship without fear of pregnancy.
This objective could
often
be most satisfactorily
implemented
through
sterilization, but
that
option usually will be unavailable
under current law. Current
law also
unnecessarily
restricts the individual's
interest in reproductive
autonomy.
Although
accorded rhetorical
deference, this interest is protected
only
if the individual is found to
be intellectually capable of making
the
medical decision. If
the person is found to be incompetent,
a court decides
whether
sterilization is in her best
interest. Yet it seems possible
that
some persons who
may be incapable
of informed
medical decisions
may be capable of meaningful
reproductive choices (to produce
a child or
avoid
pregnancy). The basis of
the restricted conception of individual
autonomy under the paternalism
model is unclear.
It may derive from a
desire
to protect vulnerable individuals
from those who threaten
their
right to procreate.
Alternatively,
it may be based
on a simplistic
analysis
of the mentally
disabled person's interest
in reproductive autonomy.
58.
The case law and commentary discuss
two seemingly contradictory objectives
of sterilization
law. On the one hand, sterilization
is authorized as a means of facilitating
reproductive choice.
On the other hand, sterilization
is characterized as a deprivation
of a fundamental right. See supra
note
20. This characterization is the basis of
the general requirement that the criteria
supporting
sterilization be established by clear and
convincing evidence. Courts cite Addington
v. Texas, 441
U.S. 418 (1979),
which required a
clear and convincing
standard in civil commitment
proceedings
because a deprivation of liberty was involved.
This analogy suggests that sterilization
is viewed by
some
courts as deprivation of procreative capacity
rather than a widely used contraceptive
option
that could be made available through a surrogate.
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
Another problematic aspect of this model is the presumed conflict of
interest in all cases between parent and child. Because every disabled
person is assumed to have an interest in procreation that conflicts with
her parents'
effort to obtain sterilization,
parental or family interests are
excluded from the decision calculus. This approach may protect the
mildly disabled person who may have an interest in making her own
choices about reproduction. But it could be harmful for the more severely
retarded person. Parents
who care for a seVerely
disabled child
assume a substantial burden. It is not clear that the law serves the interest
of such a person by augmenting that burden, especially if the presumed
interest in procreation in fact does not exist. It is also not clear
that a surrogate will be a better decisionmaker than the parents, who
presumably
know and
love the child.
It is unlikely that sterilization, the contraceptive choice of many
normal persons, is only infrequently desirable for retarded persons. Yet
sterilization will rarely be ordered in many states because most parents
will
be unable to meet the rigid criteria
set out in the sterilization
laws.
These laws erect obstacles to sterilization in order to protect a possible
interest in procreation,
60
yet they do not grapple directly with the basic
question: How can it be determined whether a given individual has this
interest? In the absence of such an inquiry, it is unclear whether the
purported safeguards serve an actual protective function or whether they
simply burden the petitioning parent and ultimately the affected individual.
6
1
II. THE INTERESTS OF THE RETARDED PERSON IN STERILIZATION:
AN AUTONOMY MODEL
This Part develops an alternative approach to sterilization of re-
tarded persons, premised on the primacy of individual and family autonomy.
First it explores the interest in reproductive autonomy and the
extent to which mental retardation affects the ability to make a meaning-
ful decision to have children or to avoid pregnancy. It then examines the
residual interests that may be important for the severely disabled person
59. See supra notes 37-50 and accompanying text.
60. See supra note 58.
61. By way of example, consider the blanket requirement that temporary alternatives be tried
and found unworkable. This requirement assumes that the person may have an interest in having
children in the future (and that a nonpermanent form of contraception is therefore desirable) without
inquiry into whether or not she actually does. A more extreme example is the rule that authorizes
sterilization only if it is a medical necessity. Such a requirement virtually forecloses
sterilization for contraceptive purposes. It presumes that sterilization benefits the individual only if
mandated by critical health needs; otherwise, preserving reproductive capacity is presumed to be of
primary importance.
59
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
who
is incapable
of autonomous
reproductive
choice-interests
involving
medical
risks
and
benefits,
human
dignity,
and
stable
family
life.
A.
Reproductive
Autonomy
and
the
Impact
of
Mental
Disability.
Analysis
of
reproductive
autonomy
62
focuses
on
the
individual's
substantive
interest
in
producing
children
or
avoiding
pregnancy
as well
as
on
her interest
in
controlling
the
decision.
It might
seem
artificial
to
examine
each
interest
separately
and
to distinguish
the
mentally
retarded
person's
interest
in
making
her
own
decisions
from
the
underlying
substantive
choices
themselves.
A
retarded
person's
disability,
however,
can
differentially
affect
her
interest
in
alternative
outcomes
because
the
decision
to
procreate
and
the
decision
not
to
procreate
each
require
different
intellectual
capabilities.
Furthermore,
a person
who
is
unable
to
make
an
autonomous
choice
about
reproduction
might
nonetheless
have
an
inter-
est
in
the
substance
of
the
decision
made
by
others
for
her.
Thus,
a
separate
analysis
of each
dimension
of the
reproductive
autonomy
inter-
est
is
indicated.
1.
The
Interest
in Preventing
Reproduction.
The
Supreme
Court
decisions
that
recognize
a woman's
right
to make
contraception
and
abortion
decisions"
are
based
on
a right
not to
procreate.
dividuals
have
a legally
sanctioned
right
to
cohabit
without
producing
unwanted
children.
66
65
63
Married
in-
Unmarried
persons
and
minors
may
not
have
the
right
to
engage
in
sexual
activity,
but
they
do have
the
right
to
avoid
the
62.
See
infra
note
92. Reproductive
autonomy
is the
constitutionally
protected
interest
individuals
have
in
private
autonomous
decisions
about
whether
or
not
to
have
a
child.
See
Roe
v.
Wade,
410
U.S. 113,
153
(1973)
(fundamental
right to
choose
abortion);
Griswold
v. Connecticut,
381
U.S.
479,
484-86
(1965)
(fundamental
right
of
marital
privacy
located
in "penumbras"
of first,
third,
fourth,
and ninth
amendments).
Reproductive
privacy
is an
important
aspect
of
a more
general
constitutional
right
of
privacy
that
extends
to
decisions
about
marriage
and
childrearing,
and
more
broadly
to protection
of bodily
integrity
and avoidance
of personal
disclosures.
In
Whalen
v. Roe,
429
U.S. 589
(1977),
the Supreme
Court
described
the right
of
privacy
as
encompassing
both
an
"interest
in avoiding
disclosure
of personal
matters"
and
a distinct
interest
in "independence
in
making
certain
kinds
of important
decisions."
Id.
at 599-60.
See
generally
L. TRIE,
AMERICAN
CONsrrIuTioNAL
LAW
921-34
(1978)
(tracing
development
of
right
to privacy
in
reproduction
decisions).
63.
This is
also true
of
many
decisions
made
for
children.
Children
have
an interest
in
the
substantive
decisions
their
parents
or the
state
make
concerning
their
health
and
safety,
even
though
they
are disabled
from
making
autonomous
choices
themselves
and
thus have
no
recognized
auton-
omy
interest.
64.
See supra
note 19.
65.
Although
the Court
has
characterized
the
right
of reproductive
privacy
as the
right
to
decide
whether
or
not to
bear
a child,
see
Eisenstadt
v. Baird,
405
U.S.
438,
453 (1972),
Professor
Robertson
correctly
points
out that
the
interest
at stake
in
abortion
and
contraceptive
cases is
the
interest
in avoiding
conception
and childbirth.
See
Robertson,
supra
note
23, at
405-06.
66.
See
Griswold
v. Connecticut,
381
U.S.
479,
481-86
(1965).
[V/ol, 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
potential
costs
of
sexual
intercourse.
67
These costs are varied and substantial. If a woman does not want to
become pregnant or
give birth, the pain, discomfort,
medical risk, and
lasting physical and emotional effects of the experience are substantial
burdens.
For an unmarried female, pregnancy
can be an embarrassing
social disability.
Responsibility for an unwanted
child can entail substantial
financial costs
and may limit the social, career,
and educational
opportunities
available to the
parent.
The
mentally retarded person may
have an interest in avoiding
preg-
nancy that is comparable to
that of the normal person. She
might want
to avoid the costs of sexual freedom-the physical burden of pregnancy
and the discomfort
of childbirth. She
might also derive a benefit from
avoiding the psychological burden caused by the birth of a child who is
unwanted or for whom she cannot care. The stress of parental responsi-
bility and the negative effect on social, educational, and employment op-
portunities are costs that are as onerous for the retarded individual as for
others.
2.
The Interest in Procreation.
In defining the constitutional
doctrine
of reproductive
privacy, the Supreme
Court has seldom focused
di-
rectly on the right to procreate.
68
Nonetheless, the importance and
constitutionally protected
status of this right are clear.
The Court has
described procreation as a "basic
civil right of man."
' 69
The
right is protected
by the constitutional tradition of family privacy and supported by
a strong historical
tradition.
70
Despite recent
concerns about population
67. The Supreme
Court has never struck down a
state statute proscribing sexual activity
between
unmarried persons. However, the Court did strike down a Massachusetts law that limited
access to contraceptives. See Eisenstadt, 405 U.S. at 454-55. In Carey v. Population Servs. Int'l, 431
U.S. 678 (1977),
the Court held that a New York law
restricting sale of nonprescription contraceptives
to
minors
was
unconstitutional.
The Court noted, however, that the
Constitution "does not bar
state regulation of the sexual behavior
of minors." Id. at 694 n. 17. The Court
stated in Eisenstadt
that it would
be unreasonable to believe that the legislature
intended to "prescribe pregnancy
as
punishment for fornication." Eisenstadt, 405 U.S. at 448. The Court has recently recognized that
protection of sexual privacy outside of marriage may be restricted in nature. In Bowers v. Hard-
wick, 106 S. Ct. 2841 (1986), it rejected the challenge of an adult homosexual arrested under a
Georgia antisodomy law for engaging in consensual sexual activity in his home. Id. at 2843. Be-
cause the opinion emphasized the homosexual nature of the activity, its broader application is
unclear.
68. Professor Robertson points out that this right has seldom been subject to state regulation;
for this reason, perhaps, it has seldom
been examined and is "ill-defined." See Robertson,
supra note
23, at 406.
69. Skinner v. Oklahoma
ex reL Williamson, 316 U.S. 535,
541 (1942). Skinner struck down,
on equal protection
grounds, an Oklahoma law that
authorized sterilization of some but not
all
habitual criminals.
70. Because of our strong tradition
of family privacy, many would reject
the notion of state
interference in a couple's freedom to have a child. Other countries have overtly discouraged procre-
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
control,
the right
to procreate remains
relatively
unambiguous
'-in contrast
to
the
right
not
to
procreate,
which
in
the
abortion
context
is
lim-
ited
by
the
interest
of
the
fetus.
Indeed,
direct
restrictions
on
reproduction
have
been
tolerated
only
when
applied
to
mentally
disabled
persons
through
involuntary
sterilization
laws.
Procreation
as
a "basic
civil
right"
is closely
linked
to
the
doctrine
of
family
privacy
and
the
right
of
parents
to
rear
their
children.
In
Stan-
ley v.
Illinois,
7
2
the
Supreme
Court
held
that
an unmarried
natural
father
who
was
rearing
his children
had
a constitutionally
protected
parental
interest.
The
Court
implicitly
linked
this
parental
interest
to procreative
rights,
stating
that
"[t]he
Court
has
frequently
emphasized
the impor-
tance
of the
family.
The
rights
to conceive
and
raise
one's
children
have
been
deemed
'essential.'
-73
Earlier,
in
Meyer
v.
Nebraska,
the
Court
defined
the
rights
"to
marry,
establish
a home
and
bring
up
children"
as liberties
protected
by
the fourteenth
amendment.
In
contrast,
the
pa-
rental
interest
of one
who
has
reproduced
without
assuming
parental
responsibilities
is
given
minimal
legal
and
constitutional
recognition.
In
Lehr
v. Robertson,
76
7
74
the
Court
held
that
a
natural
father
who
had
as-
ation
in
pursuit
of
policies
of
population
control.
The Chinese
government
offers
"one-child"
awards
that
are
available
upon
sterilization
or
a promise
not
to have
additional
children.
These
awards
take the
form
of cash
payments
and the
payment
of
the child's
medical,
educational,
and
nursery
expenses.
These
"one-child"
awards
also
may
take
the
form
of time
off
from
work
and
increased
pensions.
The
Chinese
government
imposes
penalties
upon
parents
who
have more
than
one
child
and
these
penalties
become
more
severe
as more
children
are born.
See
Goodstadt,
China's
One-Child
Family,
8
POPULATION
& DEv.
REV.
37, 48
(1982).
71.
The
reduction
in
the size
of the
American
family
in
recent
years
may
be attributed
to economics
and
better
contraception
but
not
to coercive
governmental
policies.
See
Mintz
& Kellogg,
Recent
Trends
in
American
Family
History,
81 Hous.
L. REv.
789
(1984).
72.
405
U.S.
645
(1972).
In
Stanley,
the
Court
struck
down
an
Illinois
statute
that
allowed
removal,
without
a hearing,
of the
children
of an
unmarried
father
from
the
father's
custody
upon
the mother's
death.
Id.
at 658.
The
Court
affirmed
the
father's
interest
in the
"children
he
has
sired
and
raised."
Id.
at 651.
73.
Id.
(emphasis
added).
74.
262
U.S. 390
(1923).
Meyer
was
the
first decision
to suggest
a
constitutionally
protected
interest
in family
privacy.
The Court
struck
down
a
Nebraska
law
restricting
the
use
of foreign
languages
in schools;
part
of the
Court's
rationale
was
that
the law
restricted
parental
authority.
Id.
at 400.
75.
Id.
at
399.
76.
463 U.S.
248,
263-64
(1983).
Lehr
is consistent
with
the
legal
trend
that
began
with
Stanley.
In
general,
the
courts
have
held
that
an unmarried
father's
relationship
with his
child
is to be
accorded
substantial
legal
protection
if the
father
has
assumed
parental
responsibility.
The
Supreme
Court
did
state
in Lehr,
however,
that the
"mere
existence
of a biological
link
does not
merit
equivalent
constitutional
protection."
Lehr,
463
U.S.
at 261.
The
Lehr
Court
characterized
the
natural
father's
genetic
link
as an
"opportunity"
to assume
a
unique
relationship
with
the
child.
If
he fails
to
do so,
he loses
his
parental
rights.
Id. at
262.
Because
a
natural
mother
undergoes
pregnancy
and
gives
birth,
she
may
be accorded
a superior
legal
status
over
a natural
father.
See Lehr,
463
U.S.
at 260
n.16.
Nonetheless,
she
may
lose
this
75
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
sumed no responsibility for his child was not entitled to notice of the
child's adoption by the mother's husband.
The right to procreate is the
right to produce one's own
children to
rear. The right presumes and indeed requires an intention as well as an
ability to assume the role of parent. Without this purpose and capacity,
the "right" is limited to a right to conceive, carry, and bear a child.
To
be sure, these components of the reproductive process may have in-
dependent value to the individual. For example, a man might wish to
donate sperm to perpetuate his lineage even though the children con-
ceived will remain unknown to him. A woman might want to act as a
surrogate mother because she finds pregnancy and childbirth to be meaningful
and
satisfying
experiences.
But
neither
of
these
desires,
legitimate
though they may be, implicates a fundamental right. Indeed, debate concerning
the
constitutional
implications focuses on the reproductive rights
of the prospective rearing parents.
78
It is the objective of rearing the
child-of establishing a family-that elevates the right to procreate to a
lofty status.
status if she fails to care for the child. See infra notes 80-8 1; see also Caban v. Mohammed, 441 U.S.
380 (1979); Quilloin v. Walcott, 434 U.S. 246 (1978).
77. Professor Robertson describes three aspects of the right to procreate: conception, gestation
and birth, and childrearing. Robertson, supra note 23, at 408-10. In contrast to the view expressed
in this article, Professor Robertson values each aspect of the right to procreate independently and
suggests that the benefit derived from conception or gestation should not be sacrificed because the
person lacks the ability to raise a child. Id. at 413.
78.
Surrogate mother contracts, in particular,
have been controversial. See Robertson,
Surrogate
Mothers:
Not
So
NovelAfterAll,
HASTINGS CENTER REP., Oct. 1983, at 28; Wadlington, Artifi-
cial
Conception: The Challenge for Family Law,
69 VA. L. REV. 465, 479-82 (1983).
Some courts
have rejected surrogate mother contracts as contrary to public policy "because they involve an ex-
change of money for the baby." Doe v. Kelley, 106 Mich. App. 169, 173-74, 307 N.W.2d 438, 441
(1981), cert. denied, 459 U.S. 1183 (1983). The cases focus on the contracting couple's argument
that the contract should be upheld to protect their constitutional right of reproductive privacy. See,
e.g., Surrogate Parenting Assocs. v. Commonwealth ex rel. Armstrong, 704 S.W.2d 209, 212 (Ky.
1986) ("The decision whether or not to beget or bear a child is at the very heart... of constitution-
ally protected choices."). Professor Robertson argues that infertile couples have a right to participate
in noncoital cohabitative arrangements such as surrogate contracts. Robertson, supra note 23,
at 428. The infertile
couple may have no other means to exercise
a decision to have a child except
through some noncoital arrangement. This argument is only compelling, however, if the couple
desires a child to rear. No one argues that the surrogate mother is exercising her right to procreate
by becoming pregnant through a surrogate arrangement.
Artificial insemination by a donor (AID) is characterized not as an exercise of the donor's
reproductive rights, but as a means of providing the mother with a child. See Surrogate Parenting
Assocs., 704 S.W.2d at 211-12. This characterization is appropriate because the donor has no intention
of assuming parental responsibilities. Many states have passed laws protecting the donor from
fatherly responsibilities not contemplated at the time of the contract. The Uniform Parentage Act
provides that the husband of the woman inseminated with the donor's sperm is the natural/legal
father. See U.P.A. § 5 (1986); see also CAL. CIV. CODE § 7005 (West 1983); MICH. CoMP. LAWS
ANN. § 700.111(2) (West 1980). Indeed,
the sperm donor's status as natural
father only becomes
legally relevant in the rare instance when he seeks to assume parental responsibilities. See. e.g.. C.M.
v. C.C., 152 N.J. Super. 160, 167-68, 377 A.2d 821, 824-25 (1977).
77
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
Traditional family law also
implicitly supports this analysis
of the
limited nature
of the
right to
procreate.
The law
favors biological
par-
ents over
mere
caretakers,
recognizing
the interest
that natural
parents
have
in pregnancy,
childbirth,
and
the genetic
link
to future
generations.
79
However,
biological
parents
who cannot
or will
not fulfill
their
responsibilities
as parents
lose
the legal
protection
created
by
their
status.
For
example,
abandonment
of
a child
is grounds
for
termination
of
pa-
rental
rights
in every
state.
80
Similarly,
parental
neglect
or abuse
that is
not remediable
and
that results
in intolerably
poor
child care
will also
result
in state
intervention
to remove
the child
and limit
or extinguish
the
natural parent's
legal
interest
in the
child."'
Historically,
it was commonly
believed that
mentally
retarded
per-
sons
were per
se unable
to fulfill
their responsibilities
as parents.
Even
today,
many
child protection
statutes
list mental
retardation
as a
factor
supporting
a finding
of unfitness.
82
This
presumption
of
incompetency
79. There has
traditionally
been a legal
presumption
favoring natural
parents
in custody
disputes
with
third
parties,
even if
the nonparent
has been
the child's
primary
caretaker.
See SpenceChapin
Adoption
Serv.
v.
Polk,
29
N.Y.2d
196,
201, 274
N.E.2d 431,
434, 324 N.Y.S.2d
937, 941-42
(1971).
Only if the
natural parent
is unfit will
custody go to
a nonparent over
a parent.
See Bennett
v.
Jeffreys, 40
N.Y.2d
543, 545-46,
356 N.E.2d
277, 280-81,
387
N.Y.S.2d
821, 823-24
(1976).
The
Kansas
Supreme Court
struck down
a statutory
provision
favoring the child's
"psychological
parent"
as
a violation
of the natural
parents' fundamental
right
to custody. Sheppard
v. Sheppard,
230
Kan. 146,
153-55, 630
P.2d 1121, 1127-28
(1981),
cert. denied,
455 U.S. 919
(1982). Many
statutes,
however, give
the state very
broad authority
to intervene
in families
and remove children
for abuse
and neglect.
See, eg.,
CAL. WELF.
& INST.
CODE §
300 (West
Supp. 1986).
80.
Abandonment
statutes generally
specify
a period of
time after which
the state
may termi-
nate
the parent's
rights.
See, e.g.,
MISS. CODE
ANN.
§ 93-15-103(3)(a)
(Supp.
1985)
(six months
if
child
is under age
three; one year
if child is over
age three);
MONT. CODE
ANN. §§ 41-3-102(3)(d),
41-3-609(l)(b)
(1985)
(six months);
UTAH CODE
ANN. § 78-3a-48(1)(b)
(Supp.
1986) (six
months);
VA. CODE
ANN. §
16.1-283(D)
(Supp. 1986)
(six months).
81. The state
may terminate
parental rights
if the parents
are unable
or unwilling
to remedy
the
conditions or
behavior that
led to the child's
removal.
Unless the parents'
behavior
presents a seri-
ous threat to
the child, or
is clearly not
remediable, most
states require
that before
termination
can
be ordered, services
be provided
to assist
in remediation
and the parent
be given
an opportunity
to
rectify
the
conditions
that led to
removal.
See, e.g.,
MONT.
CODE ANN.
§ 41-3-609(l)(c)(i),
(ii)
(1985); VA.
CODE ANN.
§ 16.1-283(C)(2)(b)
(Supp. 1986);
WASH. REv.
CODE
ANN.
§ 13.34.130(2)(a)
(Supp.
1986).
Many states
require that the
social service
agency submit
a foster-
care plan
providing
for remedial
services
to facilitate
the
child's return.
See,
e.g., VA. CODE
ANN.
§ 16.1-281
(Supp. 1986);
WASH.
REV. CODE
ANN. §
13.34.130(2)
(Supp. 1986).
If, after a
reasonable period
of time,
parents have
not demonstrated
progress
such as
would
make
the child's return
feasible,
the state may
hold a hearing
to terminate
the parents'
rights and
free
the child for
adoption. See,
e.g., VA. CODE
ANN. §§
16.1-283(A),
(C)(2) (Supp.
1986). The
Supreme
Court
has acknowledged
the
seriousness
of this
deprivation
by requiring
a clear
and convincing
standard
of
proof.
See
Santosky
v. Kramer,
455 U.S.
745, 747-48
(1982).
82. See
KAN. STATr.
ANN. § 38-1583(b)(1)
(Supp. 1985);
Miss. CODE
ANN. §
93-15103(3)(d)(i)
(Supp.
1985);
Mo. ANN. STAT.
§ 211.447.2(2)(a)
(Vernon
Supp. 1986);
S.C. CoDi.i
ANN.
§ 20-7-1572(6)
(Law. Co-op.
1976);
VA. CODE
ANN. § 16.1-283(B)(2)
(Supp. 1986).
Courts have
frequently based
withdrawal
of custody
or termination
of parental
rights on
par-
ents'
mental
retardation.
See In
re Jeannie
Q., 32 Cal.
App. 3d
288, 298-302,
107
Cal. Rptr.
646,
Vol. 1986:806] STERILIZATION
has been
challenged by growing evidence
that some mildly retarded individuals
may
be
able
to
function as
adequate parents.
83
Under my
analysis,
these individuals may have a protected interest in procreation.
The retarded
person's interest in having
children is more closely
linked to her intellectual and functional ability than is her interest in
avoiding pregnancy. A severely disabled person may have no affirmative
interest
at all in producing offspring,
if conception, gestation, birth,
and
childrearing
have no meaning to her. A
less-impaired person may enjoy
pregnancy or express a childlike interest in the notion of having her own
child, but may be unable to
care for a child due to her
disability.
mildly retarded person may have an interest in reproduction that approx-
imates that of the normal
individual; she may desire
children of her own
and may be capable of caring for them.
8 5
This article takes the position
that the individual who
is capable of caring for a child
has a legally protectable
interest
in procreation, and that
the individual who lacks this
capability
does
not.
8
6
653-57 (1973) (state withdrawal of retarded mother's custody of five children upheld because
mother's IQ was 61 and
two children showed evidence of malnutrition);
In re Devine, 81111. App. 3d
314, 319-20, 401 N.E.2d 616, 620-21 (1980)
(termination of parental rights upheld
where father's IQ
was 63, mother's IQ was 55, and children had been neglected); In re McDonald, 201 N.W.2d 447,
449-53 (Iowa 1972) (termination
of parental rights upheld where
father's IQ was 74, mother's IQ
was 47, and mother was unable to cope with typical child-care problems); State v. C.N.S., 319 S.E.2d
775, 780-82 (W. Va.
1984) (termination of mentally retarded parents'
rights upheld without probationary
period because
there was no reasonable likelihood of
improvement); In re C.M., 556 P.2d
514, 519 (Wyo. 1976) (termination of parental rights upheld since retarded parents would require
full-time
assistance).
83.
See supra note 30. Several commentators
have challenged the notion that mental
retarda-
tion
creates a presumption of parental unfitness.
See Shaman, supra note 30, at 72-73;
Wald, supra
note
28, at 14-15; Note, The Law and the Problem
Parent: Custody and Parental Rights
of Homosex-
ual, Mentally Retarded
and Incarcerated Parents, 16 J. FAM. L.
797 (1978); Note, Low Intelligence
of the Parent: A New Ground for State Interference with the Parent-Child Relationship?, 13 J. FAM.
L.
379
(1974).
Some courts in recent years have viewed the capabilities of mentally retarded parents in more
positive light. See, e.g., In re
Montgomery, 62 N.C. App. 343, 303 S.E.2d
324 (1983) (order terminating
parental
rights of mentally
retarded parents overturned; although
parents could not provide
some economic needs, they were providing for daily care and were able to summon help in emer-
gency situations), rev'd, 311 N.C.
101, 111, 316 S.E.2d 246, 253 (1984);
see also In re L. Children,
131 Misc. 2d 81, 499 N.Y.S.2d 587 (N.Y. Fam. Ct. 1986) (child-care agency's petition to terminate
mother's parental rights dismissed because agency had not made diligent efforts to encourage and
stengthen parental relationship
and evidence failed to establish that mental
retardation would pre-
clude mother from caring for child).
84. For example, W., an individual evaluated at the Forensic Psychiatry Clinic at the Univer-
sity of Virginia,
was a severely retarded 15 year-old girl
whose mother had recently had a baby.
W.
treated her brother like a doll and required constant supervision when she played with him. After
her brother was born, she frequently expressed a wish for her own baby.
85. See supra
notes 29-30 and accompanying
text.
86. Onora O'Neill argues that the right to procreate should be contingent on a willingness and
ability to rear or to delegate childcare responsibilities. See O'Neill, Begetting. Bearing and Rearing.
in HAVING CHILDREN
26 (0. O'Neill & W. Ruddick eds.
1979). I would argue that the parent who
84
A
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
Under
this analysis,
severely
retarded
individuals
who
are not
capable
of
fulfilling
the
basic
responsibilities
of parenthood
do not
have a
legally
protectable
interest
in
procreation.
The
meaning
of
procreation
for
such
a person
is limited
to the satisfaction
she
might derive
from
concep-
tion,
pregnancy,
and
birth and from
producing
a child
who will
be cared
for by
others. The
absence
of a legally
protectable
interest
in procreation
does
not, however,
mean
that nonconsensual
sterilization
is always
ap-
propriate
for such
a person.
It does
suggest that
the decisionmaker
should
not exaggerate
the
retarded
person's
interest in
procreation
when
determining
whether
sterilization
is appropriate.
The analysis
proposed
here,
which
focuses on
the retarded
person's
ability
to fulfill
the basic
responsibilities
of parenthood
rather
than on
some
absolute
right to
procreate,
is consistent
with
current legal
policy
regarding
contraception
and
abortion
for retarded
persons.
Despite
strong
pronouncements
in the
sterilization
context
about the
mentally
disabled person's
"right
to procreate,"
it is clear that
most
states permit
restrictions
on the
exercise
of this right
by retarded
individuals
who
are
unable to
function
as parents.
Little controversy
arises when
a parent
seeks
to
prevent
a mentally
disabled
child
from
becoming
pregnant.
Even
in those states
where
sterilization
is barred,
parents
and guardians
can consent
to
contraception
and
even abortion
for incompetent
per-
sons.
88
These
laws acknowledge
that the incompetent
person's
interest in
delegates
some responsibility
due
to a physical
disability (for
example, a
quadraplegic
parent) may
have an
interest in reproduction
and
parenting
if she is still
able to guide
the child's upbringing.
However,
the person
who cannot
fulfill any
important dimension
of the
parental role
has at most an
ephemeral
interest
in reproduction-one
that does
not merit legal
recognition.
87. It is
arguable that
parents may
not responsibly
ignore a legitimate
risk
that their mentally
disabled child
may become
pregnant. Cf
Foy v. Greenblott,
141
Cal. App. 3d
1, 8-14, 190
Cal.
Rptr. 84, 89-93
(1983) (institutionalized
individual who
became pregnant
unsuccessfully
sued facility
responsible for
her care for
failure to provide
contraception).
Normalization
policies
assume men-
tally
retarded
persons will
use contraceptives
when
engaging
in sexual
activity.
88.
The California
Supreme
Court declared
unconstitutional
a law
that prohibited
sterilization
of a
conservatee with
the conservator's
consent,
but that permitted
the
conservator to
consent to
contraception
and
abortion. See
Conservatorship
of Valerie
N., 40 Cal. 3d
143, 707 P.2d
760, 219
Cal. Rptr.
387 (1985).
The court stated:
At present
her conservators
may,
on Valerie's
behalf, elect
that she not
bear or rear
chil-
dren. As
means of avoiding
the severe
psychological
harm
which assertedly
would
result
from pregnancy,
they may choose
abortion should she
become pregnant;
they may arrange
for any
child Valerie
might bear
to be removed
from her
custody; and
they may
impose on
her other
methods of
contraception,
including
isolation from
members of
the opposite
sex.
They
are precluded
from making,
and Valerie
from
obtaining the
advantage
of, the one
choice that
may be best
for her, and
which is available
to all
women competent
to choose-
contraception
through sterilization.
Id. at 161,
707 P.2d at
771, 219 Cal.
Rptr. at 398-99.
Parents and
guardians
of mentally retarded
persons are generally
authorized
to consent
to contraceptive
and other
medical treatment
subject
to
specific
exclusions
such as sterilization,
psychosurgery,
or
electroshock
treatment. See
MONT. COtE
ANN. § 72-5-321(2)(c)
(1985);
OHio Ri.v.
Coli- ANN.
§ 5122.271(c)
(Anderson
Supp. 1985);
UTAi
Comi.i
ANN.
§ 75-5-312(l)(c)
(1978).
8 7
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
avoiding
pregnancy is more important
than a theoretical interest
in reproduction.
Only
sterilization law, responding
to its unsavory history,
seems to support
an unqualified interest in procreation
without regard to
the person's capacity
to fulfill the responsibilities
of parenthood.
Defining the level of
incompetency in parenting
skills that signals
the
absence of a protectable interest
in procreation will undoubtedly
be a
difficult and inexact
process.
89
An erroneous decision
to sterilize is probably
more
costly
than
an
erroneous
decision not to sterilize.
Therefore,
the risk of error should be tipped
in the direction of optimism
about the
individual's
potential parenting capacity.
But if the retarded person is
so
severely and irremediably impaired
that she could never provide
a child
with minimally adequate care,
91
90
and if the state would therefore
be justi-
fied
in terminating her parental rights
were she ever to have a child,
then
she has
no protectable interest
in procreation.
3.
Personal Autonomy and
the Right to Make Reproductive
Choices. The importance
of the principle of personal
autonomy in de-
fining the relationship
between the individual
and the state is well estab-
lished in our constitutional
and legal tradition.
92
Legal protection of the
freedom
of the individual to make
personal choices about religious
prac-
tice, expression
of opinion, place of residence,
and employment is
grounded
in the value of personal autonomy.
Few decisions are more
important to the individual
than the decision whether
or not to have
children.
Thus, inherent in the substantive
interests in producing and
rearing one's
own children and, alternatively,
in avoiding the burdens
of
reproduction is the individual's
interest in exercising control
over repro-
89. See infra
notes 142-43 and
accompanying text.
90. Sterilization by vasectomy
or salpingectomy may be reversible,
although this factor should
not enter the decisionmaking process because it is not predictable.
91. It is the irremediable quality of
the impairment that distinguishes the retarded
person from
others who have failed at parenting.
The fact that the normal parent
has repeatedly had children
removed from
her custody may be persuasive evidence
of an inability to provide minimally adequate
care. Her inadequacy as a parent, however,
is not necessarily irremediable; her
theoretical future
interest in procreation and in
bodily integrity would make involuntary
sterilization unacceptable.
92. John Stuart Mill's
On Liberty is the classic political philosophy
treatise on autonomy. State
control over individual action is legitimate, in Mill's view, only if necessary to prevent harm to
others. J. MILL, ON
LIBERTY 77-79 (1859). In American constitutional
law, the principle of autonomy
is
the basis of many of the
protections in the Bill of Rights. It inheres
in the broader right of
privacy which includes both notions
of autonomy and freedom from disclosure
of personal facts.
See
Whalen v. Roe, 429 U.S. 589, 598-600 (1977).
Justice Stevens has described the
individual's
"interest
in independence in making certain kinds
of important decisions" as central to
the right of
privacy. Id. at 599-600. For an examination
of the evolution and contours of the
broader constitutional
rights
of
privacy
and personhood, see L.
TRIBE, supra note 62, at 886-990. See
also Note, A
Taxonomy of Privacy:
Repose, Sanctuary, and Intimate Decision,
64 CALIF. L. REV. 1447 (1976).
834 DUKELAW JOURNAL [Vol. 1986:806
ductive
decisions.
9
3
The Supreme Court's opinions on abortion and contraception emphasize
the constitutional status of the right to make reproductive deci-
sions
free from state interference.
9 4
The Court has recognized
that this
interest is held by competent
adults
95
as well as minors who
are capable
of making their own decisions.
96
Neither the parents of a mature minor
nor a husband
may veto a woman's right
to make an autonomous choice
to
obtain
an
abortion
or
continue
the
pregnancy.
97
Until recently, mental
disability was the basis
for a blanket presumption
of incompetency.
Even libertarians such as John
Stuart Mill
assumed
that retarded persons as
a class (like children) were not
to be
regarded as autonomous persons.
98
In contrast, modem commentators
93.
The Supreme Court has stated that "[i]f
the right of privacy means anything, it
is the right
of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters
so fundamentally affecting
a person as the decision whether to
bear or beget a child." Eisenstadt v.
Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 453 (1972).
94. See id.; Carey v. Population Servs. Int'l, 431 U.S. 678, 684-85 (1977).
95. The Supreme Court focused on
protection of marital privacy in striking
down Connecti-
cut's ban on contraceptive use
in Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479,
485-86 (1965). The Court
later held that the
right extended to single persons.
Eisenstadt, 405 U.S. at 452-55.
96.
The Supreme Court has restricted the
traditional authority of parents to make
medical
decisions for their children because of the critical and urgent nature of the abortion decision and the
potential conflict of
interest between parent and child. See
City of Akron v. Akron Center for
Reproductive
Health, Inc., 462 U.S. 416, 439-40
(1983); H.L. v. Matheson, 450 U.S.
398, 405
(1981); Bellotti v. Baird, 443 U.S. 622, 643-44 (1979) (plurality opinion); Planned Parenthood v.
Danforth,
428 U.S. 52, 74 (1976). In Bellotti,
a plurality found that a minor was entitled
to a judicial
proceeding to show that
she was "mature enough and well enough
informed to make her abortion
decision ... independently
of her parents' wishes." Bellotti, 443
U.S. at 643. The Court has never
defined "maturity," and
commentators have speculated whether
it connotes competency to make an
informed medical decision, or some more general notion of maturity. See Scott, Adolescent's Reproductive
Rights:
Abortion, Contraception, and Sterilization, in CHILDREN, MENTAL HEALTH AND
THE
LAW 140 (1983). Even a young minor
cannot be presumed incompetent to make
her own
decisions. In City of Akron, the Court struck down an ordinance requiring parental consent to
abortion for minors under
age fifteen. City of Akron, 462
U.S. at 452.
The Court acknowledged
traditional parental interests,
however, when it upheld a Utah statute
requiring physicians to give notice to parents when they perform abortions on minors. Matheson,
450 U.S. at 411-13. Justice Powell, concurring,
specifically left open the question
whether this requirement
would apply
to mature minors.
Id. at 414.
97. See Danforth, 428 U.S. at 69.
98. Mill argued
that the only appropriate reason for
interfering with individual freedom is
to
avoid harm to others. He would not tolerate paternalistic intervention in decisions by "mature and
rational human beings," even if the paternalistic act would protect one from self-harm. See J. MILL,
supra note 92,
at 77-79. He specifically excluded children,
and by implication mentally disabled
persons. Id. at 22 ("Those who are still
in a state to require being taken care
of by others must be
protected against their own actions as well as against external injury."). For commentary on the
implications of Mill's philosophy for
the mentally disabled, see Monahan, John
Stuart Mill on the
Liberty of the Mentally Ili: A Historical
Note, 134 AM. J. PSYCHIATRY 1428 (1977).
See also Fein-
berg, Legal Paternalism, I CAN.
J. PHIL. 105 (1971). Feinberg explains
that autonomous actions
and decisions must be "fully voluntary"
and "chosen." Id. at I 11. Chosen actions
require delibera-
tion-a process that requires time, information, and highly developed rational faculties. Id. A deci-
Vol.
1986:806]
STERILIZATION
have challenged the presumption that mentally retarded persons are not
able
to make legally
relevant decisions.
99
Some
observers have
gone a
step further and have
suggested that disabled persons
may benefit from
the exercise
of legal rights
even if they
do not fully comprehend
the deci-
sions they make.1
°°
The law has come
to reflect these changing
attitudes in some respects.
Mentally
disabled
persons
are no longer
presumed by
the law to
be incompetent, unless
they are subject to a guardianship.
Furthermore,
some
guardianship
laws
are structured
so that the guardian
has
authority
over only a limited
range of
decisions that
are clearly beyond
the
capability
of
the
disabled
person.
10
2
Sian
is not a chosen action if it is made without
an understanding of its meaning and consequences.
Id. at 110-11.
Traditionally, mentally retarded
persons were deemed incapable of
making rational choices.
Their decisions were
not chosen and, hence,
not autonomous.
The use of a surrogate
decisionmaker
therefore did not violate autonomy.
See T. BEAUCHAMP & J. CHILDRESS,
PRINCIPLES OF BIOMEDICAL
ETHICS
63-64, 70-74 (1983).
To the extent that
the mentally disabled
person is capable
of
rational choice, of course,
autonomous decisions
are possible
and the traditional approach
is invalid.
99. See, eg.,
Wikler, Paternalism
and the Mildly
Retarded, 8 PHIL.
& PUB. AFF. 377 (1979).
Wikler asserts that relative intellectual
inferiority does not provide a general
justification for paternalistic
intervention
because otherwise
the liberty
of normal people could
be restricted and
they
could be subject
to the superior
decisionmaking of
the intellectually gifted.
Id. at 380. Other
authors
have
criticized
a general incompetency standard
as applied to medical decisions. See C. LIDZ,
A. MEISEL, E. ZERUBAVEL,
M. CARTER,
R. SESTAK & L. ROTH,
INFORMED CONSENT:
A STUDY
OF DECISIONMAKING IN PSYCHIATRY
221 (1984); Meisel, The "Exceptions"
to the Informed Consent
Doctrine: Striking
a Balance Between Competing Values
in Medical Decisionmaking, 1979 Wis.
L.
REV. 413, 440-42.
100. John Garvey
describes several theories
that would justify
ascribing constitutional
freedoms
(by which
he means rights that
involve choices) to persons
with a limited
capacity to make choices.
Garvey, Freedom
and Choice in Constitutional Law, 94
HARV. L. REv. 1756, 1762 (1981). Insofar
as it ascribes freedoms
without regard to
competency in order
to preserve human
dignity, a laissez
faire model offers the most expansive
protection. Although Garvey does
not support the laissez faire
approach, he uses it to challenge
traditional presumptions of incompetency.
Id. at 1765. He also
identifies an instrumentalist
approach, which
emphasizes that
the exercise of freedom
may promote
the
individual's development and welfare. Id.
at 1768. Garvey argues that a surrogate
decisionmaker
is
needed
if
the
choice
involves
significant
risk or if the person
is incapable of making any
choice.
The disabled person
can exercise freedoms
free from state interference
through a
surrogate
who
is close to the individual. Id. at 1778. Only
if a concerned surrogate is lacking is the
individual
subject to state authority.
101. Most laws
provide that a court can appoint a
guardian only after a competency hearing.
The statutes
make provision for
notice, the right to
counsel, and the right
to cross-examine.
See
MINN. STAT. ANN. §§ 252A.03-.10
(West 1982); N.Y. SURR. CT. PROC.
ACT § 1750 (Supp. 1986);
N.C. GEN.
STAT. §§ 35-1.8
to 1.20 (1984); W. VA.
CODE § 27-11-1 (1986),
§ 44-10A-1 (1982).
For
an overview and critique
of plenary guardianship,
see Frolik,
Plenary Guardianship:
An Analysis, a
Critique
and a Proposal for Reform, 23 ARIZ.
L. REV. 599 (1981). See also Webster,
A Study of
Guardianship in North Dakota, 60 N.D.L. REV. 45 (1984).
102. For example,
a limited guardianship
may give the guardian
authority only
to make medical
or financial decisions.
See MINN. STAT.
ANN. § 252A. 11 (West
1982); N.Y. SURR.
CT. PROC. ACT
§ 1751 (Supp.
1986); N.C. GEN. STAT. § 35-1.34 (1984);
W. VA. CODE § 44-IOA-2 (1982). For
a
good overview
with an emphasis
on limited guardianship,
see Sherman,
Guardianship: Time
for a
10 1
DUKE
LAW JOURNAL
Broad presumptions regarding the incompetency of mentally dis-
abled persons
are not appropriate because
competency can vary in two
ways. First,
competency can vary according
to the person's level of im-
pairment. The capacity
of the mildly retarded person
to make most le-
gally
relevant decisions may approximate
that of a normal
person.
Second, competency
will depend on the decision
to be made; a given indi-
vidual
might be competent
to make
some decisions
but incompetent
to
make
others.'
0
3
Even
for persons
who are otherwise
deemed
incompetent,
a presumption
of
incompetency
is
inappropriate
when
reproductive
decisions
are involved.
The Supreme
Court has recognized
that
individuals who
are not legally autonomous
for some purposes can
nonetheless have a
constitutionally
protected interest
in reproductive autonomy. The
Court
has consistently
held that
a minor who
is capable of
a mature abortion
decision need not obtain
the consent of her parents
or the state. 104 The
traditional
legal
presumption favoring
parental
authority yields
in this
situation because
of the importance
of the child's
interest in
reproductive
privacy and the
potential conffict of interest between
parent and child. A
decision made
on the minor's behalf by
a surrogate decisionmaker is
ac-
ceptable
only if the
minor is actually
incapable
of making her
own
decision.
In some sense, the retarded
individual for whom sterilization
is proposed
is
in
a
similar position.
She might be capable
of making the reproductive
decision,
even
if she is subject
to a guardianship
for other
purposes.
105 Like the
adolescent seeking
abortion,
the retarded individ-
Reassessment,
49 FORDHAM L. REv. 350 (1980). See
also Note, Limited Guardianshipfor the Mentally
Retarded,
8
N.M.L.
REV. 231
(1978).
103. Thus, an individual might be
capable of driving a car and managing
simple finances, but
incapable of making an informed medical
decision. This suggests the importance
of basing the determination
about competency on an individualized
assessment of the person's
ability to make the
specific decision
or perform the specific function in question.
Ruth Macklin and Willard Gaylin
identify three
variables as relevant to determining competency:
(1) the type of decision, (2) age
and
transient emotional
or motivational variables,
and (3) potential
for training for future
competency.
R. MACKLIN &
W. GAYLIN, supra
note 26, at 59.
104. See supra
note 96. The
comparison between
minors and mentally
disabled persons
is instructive.
Minors are subject
to a blanket presumption that they are
incompetent to make most
decisions, but the restriction
on minors' autonomy is of a limited duration
and consequently the
deprivation of rights
may be less costly.
Thus, individualized
determinations regarding
competency
on most specific
issues may simply
be too cumbersome
and inefficient.
See generally Weithorn,
Children's Capacities
in Legal Contexts,
in CHILDREN, MENTAL
HEALTH AND THE
LAW 25 (1984).
The
exception carved out for minors' abortion
decisionmaking is justified in part
because the
decision
cannot be postponed and it is critically
important to the minor's life. Unlike
most other
health care decisions,
the parents' objective cannot be presumed
to be promotion of the health of
the
child.
105. Most current
laws require a determination
about the
individual's competency
to make the
sterilization
decision-regardless
of whether she
is subject to a guardianship.
See supra notes
34-35.
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
ual who is actually
competent
to exercise meaningful
choice
should have
a legally protected
interest in reproductive
autonomy.
What then constitutes
meaningful reproductive
choice? Three distinct
decisions
are involved, each of which
requires a different level
of
competency and
intellectual functioning. First,
a disabled individual
may
be capable of
making a meaningful
decision
to have a child.
Second,
she may be competent
to make the separate
decision to forgo having a
child. Finally,
if she has competently made
the basic reproductive decision,
she may
be capable of implementing that
choice through an in-
formed medical
decision regarding
sterilization
or other forms
of birth
control.
The autonomy
interest of
the mentally
retarded person
in deciding
whether to
have a child is obscured under
laws based on the paternalism
model because
of the requirement
of a threshold
inquiry
into whether the
person
is competent
to make an informed
medical
decision about
sterilization.
If
she
is
not,
the
law
presumes
that
she
is
incapable
of making
the
reproductive
decision and that a
surrogate (the court) must weigh
her
interests and make the
decision for her.
106
The ability
to make an informed
medical
decision
involves
a level of cognitive
functioning
that
many mentally retarded
persons lack.107 However,
a person who is un-
able to make this implementing
decision might nonetheless
be capable of
making
the underlying decision
to have or to forgo having a
child.
This
decision is
fundamentally
different from
the medical sterilization
decision
and requires different capabilities.
By specifying competency
to
make the
medical decision as the threshold
requirement, laws based
on
the
paternalism model
distort and
even foreclose
the inquiry into
the in-
dividual's ability
to make
the decision
whether to have
a child.
Under
the autonomy
model, competency
to make
a meaningful
choice
to procreate rests on the
individual's ability to fulfill the
basic
responsibilities
of parenthood. A mildly
impaired person may have this
ability regardless
of whether
she is legally
competent to
make medical
decisions regarding sterilization.
Her interest in making
her own repro-
In a
few states, a sterilization decision can be
based on a general designation of incompetency.
See
In re Penny N., 120 N.H.
269, 271, 414 A.2d 541,
543 (1980).
106. See supra notes
34-35 and accompanying
text.
107. See supra
note 26 and accompanying
text; see also
infra notes 112-18
and accompanying
text (discussing cognitive capacity
needed for medical decisionmaking).
108. My
colleague Ken Abraham
suggests that
individuals who
are unable to make
medical
decisions will not
be competent parents
because such individuals
would be unable
to make informed
medical
decisions for their children. The point
is well taken; however, if a parent could
accomplish
all other critical
parental tasks, some
mechanism could be
devised to compensate
for this disability.
Moreover,
the distinction
between the two types
of competency is
useful for analytical
purposes.
The
most important inquiry in determining
the individual's interest in reproductive autonomy
is
whether
she will ever want
a child. The medical
competency
issue obscures this
inquiry.
10 8
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
ductive
decisions
should
be
legally
protected.
On the
other
hand,
a severely
disabled
person's
childlike
wish
for
a
baby
does
not
signify
a
meaningful
choice.
A decision
to
have
a
child
is,
most
importantly,
a
decision
to
become
a parent-to
assume
a role
that
requires
a
minimal
level
of competency.
If
the
individual
lacks
this
capability
and
the
state
would
predictably
intervene
to
remove
any
child
produced
in order
to
protect
it, then
the
choice
to
have
a
child
is
not
a legally
protectable
exercise
in personal
autonomy.
10 9
Thus,
the
interest'
in autonomy
is
derivative
of
the
underlying
interest
in
having
children.
If
the
retarded
individual
lacks
the
ability
to
exercise
the
substantive
interest,
she
lacks
the
interest
in
making
the
choice.
110
The
disabled
person
also
may
be
capable
of
making
an autonomous
decision
not
to
have
a child.
She
may
clearly
express
a stable
preference
not
to
have
a
child
based
on
a desire
not
to
assume
the
burdens
of
pregnancy
or
the
responsibilities
of
rearing
a
child.
Unlike
the
decision
to
procreate,
the
decision
to avoid
pregnancy
involves
an underlying
substantive
interest
that
does
not
itself
require
a
minimal
level
of
competency.
11
1
Thus,
the
ability
to make
the
decision
to
avoid
pregnancy
rests
solely
on
a
capacity
for
rational
decisionmaking
and
not
on any
underly-
ing
functional
capability.
Rationality
may
be
measured
by
the
clarity
and
consistency
of the
expressed
preference
not
to have
a child.
The
preference
may
be
to prevent
pregnancy
in the
immediate
future
or
it
may
directly
or
indirectly
reflect
a desire
not
to
have
children.
The
individual
who
is
competent
to
make
her
own
reproductive
choice
may
also
be competent
to
implement
that
choice
by
making
the
medical
decision
about
sterilization
or
other
contraceptive
options.
With
respect
to
the
contraception
decision,
her
autonomy
interest
has
two
dimensions.
First,
the
decision
is
an
exercise
of
reproductive
autonomy.
She
is
making
a
decision
about
whether
to
permanently
or temporarily
prevent
pregnancy
through
a
chosen
medical
procedure.
Second,
the
competent
individual
has
an
overlapping
but
distinct
interest
in
main-
taining
control
over
health
care
decisions.
She
has
an
interest
in
weighing
the
benefits
and
risks
to
her
health
of
various
medical
and
surgical
109.
In
theory,
a person
who
is
incapable
of
parenting
because
of
mental
disability
may be
capa.
ble
of making
a "rational"
decision
to
procreate
reflecting
a
basic
understanding
of what
it
means
to
have
a child-costs,
benefits,
risks,
etc. That
decision
has
little
meaning,
however,
if she
could
never
function
as a
parent.
In
reality,
it
is probable
that
few will
lack
the
functional
capability
while
possessing
the
cognitive
decisional
ability.
110.
The
underlying
interest
itself
often
defines
the individual's
interest
in
control
over
making
the
decision.
For
example,
minors
do
not have
the
freedom
to make
the decision
to
marry
because
they
are
deemed
incapable
of
assuming
the
responsibility
of
marriage.
They
lack
the underlying
substantive
interest
and
therefore
lack
the
interest
in making
the
decision.
111.
Indeed,
avoiding
pregnancy
may
promote
the
physical,
psychological,
and
social
welfare
of
a profoundly
impaired
person.
See
H.
KAPLAN
& B.
SADOCK,
supra
note
26, at
852.
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol.
1986:806]
STERILIZATION
procedures and reaching a decision whether or not to undergo a given
treatment.11
2
Applying
the preferred
legal
standard,
competency
to give
(or
withhold) informed
consent
to a medical procedure
is based
on an
appreciation
of the
nature and purpose
of the procedure,
its risks
and
benefits, and
its consequences
in comparison
with
available alter-
natives.
113
Some individuals
who are
capable of making
a meaningful
reproductive
decision
will
not
be
capable
of
making
the
medical
decision
necessary
to
implement
the underlying
choice.
114
It
has been suggested
that informed
medical
decisionmaking
requires
the
ability
to engage
in formal
operational thinking.
According
to Piaget,
this is the highest
stage of
cognitive
development
and is achieved
by normal
individuals between
the
ages of
eleven and
fourteen.
1
1
5
At this
stage one
has the
capability
to
conceptualize
several
abstract
possibilities
and
consider
the consequences
of
various courses
of action.1
6
Many
mentally
disabled persons
lack this
capability
and
are thus
unable
either to
appreciate
the consequences,
112.
Commentators have
argued that the informed
consent requirement
for medical
treatment is
also
based on protecting
personal autonomy.
The individual must
understand the
procedure, its
risks, benefits, and
alternatives in order
to control what will
be done to her body.
See Capron,
Informed
Consent in Catastrophic
Disease Research
and Treatment,
123 U. PA. L. REV.
340, 364-76
(1974).
In a leading
case defining the contours
of modern informed
consent law,
Natanson v. Kline,
186
Kan.
393, 350 P.2d 1093
(1960), the Kansas
Supreme Court stated:
"Anglo-American
law starts
with the premise of
thorough-going self-determination.
It follows
that each man
is considered to be
master
of his own body, and
he may, if he be of
sound mind, expressly
prohibit the performance
of
life-saving
surgery,
or other medical
treatment." Id.
at 406-07, 350 P.2d
at 1104.
113. There
are several standards
of competency
to make medical
decisions. Under the
lowest
standard, a
competent individual
is one who is capable
of expressing a preference.
A second
stan-
dard focuses
on whether the decision
itself is rational;
if it is, it is deemed
competent. Some
commentators
have
suggested that this
standard is typically
used in psychiatric hospitals.
The decision
to accept treatment
is deemed competent;
to refuse treatment
suggests incompetency.
See Meisel,
supra
note 99,
at 443-45. A
third standard
looks at the
rationality of
the decisionmaking
process.
The fourth
and prevailing
standard
is the so-called
appreciation
standard, which
measures
the patient's
inferential
as well as factual
understanding or
recall. See Weithorn,
Developmental Factors
and Competence
to Make Informed
Treatment Decisions,
CHILDREN & YOUTH
SERVICES, SpringSummer
1982,
at 85, 89-95.
Several commentators
have suggested
that appreciation requires
the
ability to think abstractly
and draw inferences
about the implications
of the proposed
treatment. See
Applebaum
& Roth,
Clinical Issues
in the Assessment
of Competency,
138 AM.
J. PSYCHIATRY
1462,
1463-65 (1981);
Weithorn, supra
note 104, at 35.
114. The
Forensic Psychiatry
Clinic at the University
of Virginia,
for example, evaluated
a wo-
man, B., age 35
with one child, who
had over a number
of years consistently
said that she wanted
"no
more
babies."
Attempts
to
use
birth
control
pills
and
an
IUD
had
caused
substantial
medical
problems.
Her competency
to make the sterilization
decision was questionable,
however,
because
she
could not think abstractly
about permanence
and about not being
able to change her
mind in the
future.
115.
See H. KAPLAN & B. SADOCK,
supra note 26, at
58-59.
116. See Weithorn,
supra note 104,
at 37. Weithorn
and Campbell conducted
research on the
competency of
normal children to
make medical decisions.
They found that,
by age 14, minors
reasoned
about medical
decisions much like
adults. See Weithorn
& Campbell, The Competency
of
DUKE
LAW JOURNAL
risks,
and benefits of
sterilization or
to weigh the
alternatives.
If the
individual
is incapable
of giving
informed consent
to contraceptive
treat-
ment,
her reproductive
decision
may be
undermined.
11 8
Therefore,
the
law
should facilitate
her reproductive
choice
through a surrogate
who
can consent
to
the medical
procedure
for her.
The
retarded person
who
is competent
to
make autonomous
repro-
ductive and
medical decisions
should not
be subject to
paternalistic supervision.
In
light
of the overriding
interest in
personal
autonomy,
the
individual
should be
free to
weigh whatever
other
interests
are subjectively
important
to her,
regardless of
what an objective
decisionmaker
would consider
to
be in her
best interest.
For example,
she
is free
to
choose
to have a
child even
if a medical
condition
makes
this decision
risky.
If her decision
is competent,
its wisdom
should not
be scrutinized.
4.
Summary.
In contrast
to
the paternalism
model,
the
autonomy
model
defines
the
interest
in reproductive
autonomy both
more precisely
and
more expansively
by focusing
on the
person's capability
to
make
the reproductive
choice.
The mentally retarded
person
has an interest
in
reproductive
autonomy
if
she
is
capable
of
making a meaningful
decision
about whether
or not to
have a child. Her
interest in a
meaningful
choice to procreate
is derived
from her substantive
interest
in repro-
duction. If
she is capable
of rearing a child,
her interest
in procreation
and in the decision
to have children
is indistinguishable
from
that held by
the normal
person. Her interest
in the decision
not to have
children rests
on her ability
to make a
meaningful choice
to avoid pregnancy.
The indi-
vidual who
is capable
of making
an autonomous
reproductive
choice
might
or might
not be capable
of
making the
implementing
medical
deci-
sion;
this requires the
cognitive ability
to give or withhold
informed
consent
to
the medical
procedure.
Children and Adolescents
to Make
Informed Treatment
Decisions, 53 CHILD
DEv. 1589, 1595-96
(1982);
see also supra
note 26.
117.
Persons who are
more than mildly retarded
are unlikely
to have this capability.
It is unclear
whether mildly
retarded persons
would be able to
engage in these cognitive
processes. See R.
MACKLIN
& W. GAYLIN,
supra note
26, at 59-62. The
cognitive
developmental
approach to
mental
retardation
suggests by definition
that mentally retarded
persons do not
reach the highest stage
of
cognitive
development-formal
operational
thinking. See supra
note 26 and accompanying
text. I
am reluctant
to engage in
such a broad
categorization,
however, given
the variations
in conceptualiz-
ing both mental
retardation and
competency.
118. The
individual described
supra note 114 is a
good example. Sterilization
was not allowed
because she
was capable
of caring for
her child, and
thus could
not meet one
of the mandatory
criteria
under Virginia
law. See VA. CODE
ANN. § 54-325.13(4)
(1982).
[Vol. 1986:806
I7
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
B. Residual
Interests
of the Severely
Retarded
Person.
Some
mentally
disabled persons
are not competent
to make
repro-
ductive
decisions
for themselves.
A decision about
sterilization
made on
behalf
of an individual
in this category
violates
no interest in
reproduc-
tive autonomy;
when a person
is incapable
of making her
own decision,
others must
determine
whether sterilization
is in her
best interest.
Sterilization
is not necessarily
the appropriate
choice
simply because
the
individual
has no meaningful
interest in reproduction,
and
therefore has
a presumptive
interest in
avoiding pregnancy.
The desirability
of the
procedure
may depend
on nonreproductive
considerations
such as medical
risks
and
benefits,
human
dignity, privacy,
and
family continuity
and
stability.
1. Medical
Risks and
Benefits.
The person who
is unable
to
make her own
medical decisions
has an interest
in a decision
about con-
traception
that
most
effectively
promotes
her medical
needs.
Risk, con-
venience, comfort,
intrusiveness,
and effectiveness
are variables
that may
be relevant
in treatment
choice. One option
is long-term
use of birth
control
pills. However,
this
practice
is generally
not advised
for normal
women;
its medical risks
are now being
studied.
120
Use of an intrauterine
device also entails
substantial
risk;121 indeed,
most models
have been
119. The
term "best interest"
is often associated
with a judicial
decisionmaker exercising
the
state's
parens patriae
authority.
This article
uses the term
to encompass
decisions by
parents as well.
The
law's objective is for
the decisionmaker,
whether court or parent,
to make the sterilization
decision
that
is best for the
incompetent person.
120.
Oral contraceptives
such
as the Pill
must be taken
on a regular
schedule and
may present
several risks
to the user including
heart disease, diabetes,
thrombophlebitis,
and hypertension.
See
CONTRACEPTIVE TECHNOLOGY,
supra note
1, at 49-50, 56-61.
But see Sattin, Rubin,
Wingo, Webster
& Ory,
Oral Contraceptive
Use and the Risk of
Breast Cancer, 315
NEW ENG. J. MED.
405
(1986) (study finding
no correlation between
long-term use of
oral contraceptives and
breast cancer).
Minor
side effects
such as weight
gain and
frequent headaches
are also
possible. See
CONTRACEP-
TIVE
TECHNOLOGY,
supra note 1, at 55-56.
121. IUDs
are inserted into the
uterus and prevent
an embryo from attaching
to the uterine
wall.
The principle
risks associated
with IUDs
are: discomfort,
increased
bleeding,
spontaneous
expulsion,
increased
frequency
of urine and pelvic
infection, and pregnancy
failures. See
CONTRACEP-
TIVE TECHNOLOGY,
supra note 1, at
202-10.
Concerns
about the safety
of the IUD
have grown
in recent years
and the
device may
not be
available
in the future.
Some commentators
feel that for nulliparous
women (women
who have
never
been pregnant), the
use of an IUD may
double the risk of
tubal infertility in comparison
with
other
methods of contraception.
See Cramer,
Schiff, Schoenbaum,
Gibson, Balisle, Albrecht,
Stillman,
Berger,
Wilson,
Stadel
& Seibel, Tubal
Infertility and the Intrauterine
Device, 312
NEw ENG.
J. MED.
941, 947
(1985). A.H.
Robins, Inc.,
producer of the
Dalkon Shield,
has incurred
massive
liability in a class
action settlement
with women seriously
injured by this
device. Robins filed
a
Chapter I I bankruptcy
petition after
incurring liability
of $1.1 billion in litigation
costs with 5,000
suits pending.
Another manufacturer
of IUDs, G.D.
Searle & Co., is facing
potentially disastrous
litigation.
Over 600 suits were
pending as of October
1985. See Glaberson,
Did Searle
Close Its
Eyes?.
Bus. WK., Oct.
14, 1985, at 120. Both
Searle and Ortho Pharmaceutical
Corp.
have removed
11 9
DUKE
LAW JOURNAL
withdrawn
from
the
market.
This
risk
is
increased
if the
physician
uses
a
general
anesthetic
while
inserting
the
device
(a
common
practice
with
severely
retarded
women
because
the
patient
may
otherwise
resist
the
procedure).
122
The
experimental
drug
Depo-Provera
is another
form
of
contraception
used
for
retarded
women.
123
Again,
the
effects
of
longterm
use
are
unclear.
Finally,
if
ineffective
(perhaps
less
risky)
birth
con-
trol
options
are
chosen,
the
risks
associated
with
pregnancy,
abortion,
and
childbirth
must
be considered.
124
None
of these
contraceptive
options
is
a clearly
superior
medical
alternative
to salpingectomy
or
other
nonintrusive
forms
of
sterilization.
125
Thus,
the
individual's
interest
in
the
optimal
medical
decision
may
be
promoted
as
well
by
nonintrusive
forms
of
sterilization
as by
the
available
contraceptive
alternatives.
Laws
based
on the
paternalism
model
fail
to
separate
the
individ-
ual's
reproductive
interest
from
her
interest
in
the medical
decision.
Be-
their
IUDs
from
the
market.
The
only
IUD
currently
being
sold
in
the United
States
is a little-used
device
that
releases
hormones
in
much
the same
way
as the
Pill. Dulea,
Liability
Crisis
Complicates
Contraception,
N.Y.
Times,
May
19, 1986,
at
B8, col.
1.
122.
Insertion
of
an IUD
may
be
difficult
with
a retarded
woman
as
some
pain
is involved,
which
she
may
not understand.
Some
gynecologists
use
general
anesthesia
when
performing
this procedure
because
of concern
that
perforation
or other
injury
will
result
if the woman
is agitated.
See
Melton
& Scott,
Evaluation
of Mentally
Retarded
Persons
for
Sterilization:
Contributions
and Limits
of
Psychological
Consultation,
15
PROF.
PSYCHOLOGY:
RES.
&
PRAC.
34,
42
(1984).
Professors
La Veck
and
de la
Cruz,
writing
before
the
risks of
IUDs
became
known,
recommended
the
IUD
as
the
optimal
contraceptive
option
for
mentally
retarded
women
since
it
requires
no motivation
or
intellectual
skills.
See
La Veck
&
de ]a
Cruz,
Contraception
for
the Mentally
Retarded:
Current
Methods
and
Future
Prospects,
in
HUMAN
SEXUALITY
AND THE
MENTALLY
RE-
TARDED
96-97
(F.
de ]a
Cruz
& G.
La Veck
eds.
1973).
123.
Depo-Provera
is a
substituted
progesterone
that
suppresses
ovulation.
It is effective
for
three
months
when
injected
intramuscularly.
The
Food
and
Drug
Administration
has
not
yet approved
Depo-Provera
for
contraceptive
use
in
the United
States
because
it causes
breast
tumors
in
beagles.
See
R. HATCHER
& G.
STEWART,
CONTRACEPTIVE
TECHNOLOGY
1982-1983,
at 66-67
(1982).
Use of
the drug
also
causes
minor
side
effects
such
as
disruption
of
normal
menstruation
and
irregular
and
unpredictable
bleeding.
The woman
may
experience
weight
gain and
a delayed
return
of fertility
once
treatments
are stopped.
See
id. at
67.
124.
The
medical
risk,
pain,
and
anxiety
associated
with
pregnancy
and
birth
may
be greater
for
one
who
does
not understand
the
process
and
cannot
look
forward
to the
fruits
of the
effort.
Abor-
tion
has some
risks
that
increase
as the
term
of the
pregnancy
progresses.
Second
trimester
abortions
have
risks
comparable
to
the risks
of childbirth.
See
id. at
7. For
teens,
childbirth
has
five
times
the
mortality/morbidity
rate of
a first
trimester
abortion.
Id.
125.
Some
forms
of tubal
ligation
may
be
performed
on
an outpatient
basis.
It leaves
minute
scars,
involves
minimal
discomfort,
and
allows
for a
rapid
recovery
with
a quick
return
to normal
activity,
including
sex. The
most
popular
form
of tubal
ligation
is
laparoscopy,
which
involves
extremely
rare
risks
of
hemorrhage,
electric
shock,
perforation
of
organs,
puncture
of
blood
vessels
and
skin,
and
internal
burns.
The current
mortality
rate for
the
laparascopic
procedure
is 10
deaths
per
100,000
procedures.
See
id. at
195-96.
The only
complications
associated
with
vasectomy,
an outpatient
procedure,
are
skin
discolora-
tion,
swelling,
pain,
and
hematoma
(a mass
of
clotted
blood
from
injured
blood
vessels
in
loose
connective
tissues
of the
scrotum).
Hematomas
usually
occur
in
less than
one
percent
of
all vasecto-
mies.
See
id.
at
190.
(Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
cause sterilization extinguishes
reproductive capacity, it
is presumed to
be inherently more intrusive and "drastic" than any nonpermanent form
of contraception, and is only allowed as a last resort. However, for the
person who has no interest in having children, some forms of sterilization
are no more "drastic" in a
medical sense than other contraceptive
options.
For
the severely disabled person
who lacks a potential interest
in
having children,
assessment of sterilization
as a treatment alternative
should be made independently of the interest in reproduction itself.
However, more intrusive forms of sterilization, such as hysterectomy,
are not comparable
in a medical sense
to other contraceptive options.
Some parents might
seek hysterectomy
126
for a severely
retarded
daughter because she has difficulty managing menstrual hygiene tasks or
because she
experiences distress with menstrual
periods.
1 27
tion,
the threat to the retarded person's
interest in the optimal
medical
decision is greatly increased because the procedure is major surgery and
involves enhanced medical risk. Furthermore, medical judgment may
not serve its traditional
protective function. Physicians
can generally be
relied on
to recommend the treatment
that best promotes the patient's
medical welfare with
minimal risk. However, a gynecologist
might recommend
a
hysterectomy
for a severely retarded young woman, based not
on the woman's gynecological
needs, but on an evaluation
of her intellectual
capabilities,
an issue on which
gynecologists have little expertise.
To
the extent that risk is incurred beyond that indicated by her medical
needs,
intrusiveness is increased and
justification of the decision
on the
ground
that
it promotes
the
patient's
interests
becomes
more
difficult.
126.
Although hysterectomy is 100% effective
as a method of birth control, some
authorities
flatly state that because of the risks, hysterectomy is never appropriate for contraceptive purposes.
See Amirikia & Evans,
Ten-year Review of Hysterectomies: Trends,
Indications, and Risks, 134 AM.
J. OBsTETRICS & GYNECOLOGY
431, 432-33 (1979) (study of 6400
hysterectomies described signifi-
cant complications including infection (4.7%), bleeding (1.4%), risks from transfusion (12%), bladder
and bowel injury
(0.6%), thromboembolisms (0.6%)
and death (0.26%)). Usually
hysterectomies are only
performed for sterilization purposes
when there are other gynecologic
problems present as well. See M. SAIDI & C. ZAINIE, FEMALE STERILIZATION: A HANDBOOK FOR
WOMEN 44 (1980). Many current laws
implicitly discourage hysterectomies by
requiring that the
sterilization procedure chosen be the least restrictive alternative. See, eg., VA. CODE ANN. § 54-
325.12 (1982).
127. Research indicates that moderately retarded persons with proper training can manage all
aspects of menstrual hygiene. Severely
retarded women can learn all aspects except
initiation. See
Hamilton, Allen, Stephens & Davall, Training Mentally Retarded Females to Use Sanitary Napkins,
MENTAL RETARDATION, Feb. 1969,
at 40, 43; see also Melton & Scott, supra
note 122, at 42-43.
128. A major surgical procedure with significant medical risk may be medically necessary to
save the person's life or restore her health. It is the discrepancy between the nonautonomous patient's
medical needs and the risk associated with the procedure that raises concerns about whether
her welfare is promoted.
An analogous problem arises in medical research on incompetents and children. If an individ-
ual is not competent to consent to the risks of research, the procedure may represent an unwarranted
In this situa-
128
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
2. Human Dignity and
Privacy. The severely disabled
person
who is incapable of autonomous choice has an interest in being treated
with human dignity and in avoiding unnecessary intrusions into her pri-
vacy by those who make the sterilization decision for her.
129
interest is threatened
if she is subjected to a medical
procedure against
her will. Furthermore, protection of privacy requires that personal in-
quiry and disclosure in the decisionmaking process be limited, and that
only
those persons whose participation
is needed to make a good
decision
be
involved.
1
3
0
Some individuals who are not capable of making their own reproductive
decisions
will object to a
proposed sterilization. Such
objection
can reflect varying levels of comprehension and may have several
sources. The individual might adhere to a childlike wish for a baby. She
might be afraid of doctors, hospitals, or pain. Whatever the source of her
protest, the medical procedure
will be more offensive
to her dignity then
if she were agreeable. In general, any objection reflecting basic understanding
signifies
that the procedure intrudes on the individual's dignity.
Although the protest should not necessarily determine the outcome, it
does reflect an interest of the individual that should be considered in any
decision
designed
to
promote
her
welfare.
31
In general,
the severely retarded
person has a reduced expectation
of
personal privacy. Others are
involved in intimate decisions
affecting her
life, including medical decisions, to a greater extent than is the case with
the normal person.
Even if she is capable of
making her own decisions,
bodily
intrusion because its purpose is not solely
health promotion. See Kaimowitz
v. Michigan
Dep't of Mental Health, 42 U.S.L.W. 2063, 2063 (Mich. Cir. Ct. July 10, 1973) (involuntarily committed
patient cannot consent to experimental "high risk-low benefit" psychosurgery).
129. The notion of "respect for persons" extends beyond respect for individual autonomy to a
recognition of the humanity
of nonautonomous persons. In Kantian
terms, persons should not be
treated as a means to another end. See T. BEAUCHAMP & J. CHILDRESS, supra note 98, at 7.
130. The Supreme Court has described two dimensions of the right of privacy: independence in
making important personal decisions, and freedom to prevent disclosure of personal facts. See
Whalen v. Roe, 429 U.S. 589,
599-600 (1977). The incompetent person
lacks the first dimension, but
this does not mean that the second dimension should routinely be disregarded. Many current laws
require judges, attorneys, and
others to scrutinize the mentally retarded
person's competency,
parenting ability, sexual activities, reproductive capacity, and contraceptive practices. See supra
notes 35-48 and accompanying text. Such scrutiny is justified only if it serves some beneficial
purpose.
131. Federal regulations governing medical research involving children recognize that an incom-
petent person's agreement or objection to a medical procedure may be significant. See 45 C.F.R.
§§ 46.401-.409 (1985). These regulations require the parents' permission and tle minor's assent for
most types of research. Assent
is not defined, but Professor Weithorn has
described it as knowledgeable
agreement. Weithorn, Children's Capacities to Decide About Participation in Research, IRB,
Mar.-Apr. 1983, at 1, 2. Weithorn suggests that children become capable of assent at age six. Id. at
5. If a child capable of assent
protests, the protest will be respected unless
the research offers the
child a direct health benefit that is otherwise unavailable. 45 C.F.R. § 46.408(a) (1985).
[Vol. 1986:806
Her dignity
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
she will be
allowed to do so only after
intrusive scrutiny of her competency.
132
Although most medical decisions will involve only her parents
or guardian and a physician, the sterilization decision often involves an
expanded group of participants.
The potential for
infringement of her
privacy interest
is great if the law requires rigorous
procedural protections
and
substantive
findings.
133
Under the
paternalism model,
both individual
and
family privacy
are largely
ignored
in the process
of
evaluating the desirability
of sterilization. Although
some intrusion on
privacy is necessary, this
interest should not be
unnecessarily
sacrificed.
134
3. The Interest
of the Retarded Person
in Family Stability. Many
parents
abandon or
institutionalize
their mentally
retarded children
when the disability becomes
apparent or burdensome;
1 3
5
their
children in foster
care. The
disabled person
whose parents
have
accepted the responsibility
of caring for her at home
is very likely better
off
than one subjected
to any of
these alternatives;
she has a substantial
interest
in continued
care by her parents.
Family
stability is thus
an in-
terest held by the child as
well as the parents. This stability
may be
affected by the
level of stress
that attends the
burden of caring
for a re-
tarded child. 136 It can be threatened
by concerns about the
child's sexu-
ality.
The welfare of a severely retarded
person who has no interest
in
reproduction
may be promoted if her parents'
concerns about pregnancy
132.
Note the parallel here to the procedures
set forth in Bellotti v. Baird, 443 U.S.
622, 643-44
(1979) (plurality opinion),
for determining
the maturity of the
minor who seeks an
abortion. For a
discussion of
Bellotti, see supra
note 96.
133.
See supra notes 37-50
and accompanying
text.
134.
Application of the least restrictive alternative
doctrine is relevant to intrusions into
personal
privacy.
See Hoffman & Foust,
Least Restrictive
Treatment of the Mentally
Ill: A Doctrine
in Search
of its Senses,
14 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1100, 1102-03 (1977).
Any infringement of a constitutionally
protected interest
should be restricted
to that necessary
to accomplish the
legitimate purpose.
Id. at
1101. This doctrine
has been applied to
involuntary treatment
of mentally ill patients.
Id. at 1102.
Civil commitment
law in many
states includes a directive
that the least
restrictive treatment
be
utilized. Id. at 1112.
135. The normalization
trend has encouraged parents
to rear their mentally retarded children
at
home. See
supra note 28. Nonetheless,
family stress
may increase as the
child grows older, and
may
ultimately
prompt a decision to
remove the child from
the home. For boys,
concern among
neighbors
about aggressiveness may be a problem.
See E. SCHULMAN, supra note 26,
at 100. For girls,
the parents' dominant
concern may
be pregnancy.
136.
For a discussion
of the stresses involved
for parents and
siblings who live with
a retarded
child, see E. SCHULMAN, supra note
26, at 96-125. See also J. GREENFELD,
A CHILD CALLED
NOAH:
A FAMILY JOURNEY
(1972) (personal
account of father
of autistic child). Families
with a
mentally
disabled child
frequently experience
marital and financial
stress. See Dunlap
& Hollinsworth,
How
Does a Handicapped Child Affect the Family?
Implications for Practitioners, 26 FAM.
COORDINATOR
286 (1977); Sherman
& Cocozza, Stress in
Families of the Developmentally
Disabled:
A Literature
Review of Factors
Affecting the Decision
to Seek Out-of-Home
Placements, 33
FAM.
REL. 95
(1984).
others place
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
are
alleviated.
Her
interest
in
family
stability
is substantial
and
therefore
may
warrant
legal
protection.
The
individual's
interest
in
family
stability
should
become
legally
relevant
with
respect
to
the
sterilization
decision
only
if the
individual
is
so seriously
impaired
that
she
will
never
be
capable
of making
her
own
reproductive
decisions.
For
example,
a
mildly
retarded
young
woman
whose
parents
respond
to
her
promiscuous
behavior
by
seeking
steriliza-
tion
might
have
an
interest
in reducing
family
stress;
if sterilization
is
proscribed,
her
parents
might
respond
with
abusive
treatment,
unreason-
able
restrictions
of her
freedom,
or
even
relinquishment
of
their
parental
role.
However,
this
young
woman
will
one
day
be
independent
and
might
at
that
time
want
to
have
children.137
Thus
her
future
capability
to
make
decisions
for
herself
precludes
legal
consideration
of
her
present
interest
in
family
continuity.
Using
sterilization
to
promote
family
stability
is
as
offensive
here
as
it
would
be
in
the
case
of a
promiscuous
normal
adolescent.
C.
The
Autonomy
Model
and
the
Deficiencies
of
Current
Law.
The
analytic
framework
developed
in
this
Part
suggests
that
current
law
falls
short
of
its objective
of promoting
sterilization
decisions
that
reflect
the
interests
of
mentally
disabled
persons.
The
preoccupation
with
correcting
the
abuses
of
the
past
in combination
with
a superficial
analysis
of
the
interests
at
stake
has
engendered
significant
distortions.
Three
problems
result
from
the
paternalism
model's
presumption
that
the
primary
interest
at stake
is the
interest
in
procreation.
First,
in
its
effort
to protect
the
mentally
retarded
person
from
wrongful
sterilization,
the
law
unduly
restricts
her
right
of
self-determination.
As
I
have
shown,
if only
persons
competent
to
make
the
medical
decisions
are
deemed
capable
of
making
reproductive
decisions
for
themselves,
some
persons
who
do
have
an
interest
in
autonomy
will
find
themselves
subject
to the
authority
of
another
decisionmaker.
That
is,
an individual
who
is
capable
of
deciding
the
more
basic
issue-whether
or
not
to have
a
child-will
sometimes,
in
the name
of
protection,
be
subject
to a
surrogate
decisionmaker.
137.
This
situation
was presented
in
Stump
v. Sparkman,
435
U.S.
349
(1978).
In
that
case,
a
mother,
prompted
by
concern
over
her
teenage
daughter's
promiscuity,
successfully
petitioned
a
judge
for
the daughter's
sterilization.
The
daughter
was described
as
"somewhat
retarded,"
although
she
was
promoted
each
year
with
her public
school
class.
Id.
at 351.
She
was
told
that
the
surgical
procedure
was
an
appendectomy
and
did
not learn
that
she
had
been
sterilized
until
she
married
and
found
that
she was
unable
to
become
pregnant.
Id.
at 353.
The
daughter
sued
her
mother
and
the judge
who
authorized
the procedure.
The Supreme
Court
upheld
the
judicial
immu-
nity of
the
judge,
who
had
authorized
the sterilization
absent
statutory
authority.
Id. at
364.
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
Second, laws
based on the paternalism
model
treat sterilization
as an
infringement
of the
right to procreate
rather than
as a means of
exercis-
ing the
right not to procreate.138
It is
ironic that a legal
rule designed
to
protect mentally
disabled persons
impairs the
fundamental
right to avoid
pregnancy-a
right
that others
can exercise
freely.
Laws premised
on
a
strong presumption
that every
retarded person
has an interest
in procrea-
tion
make consideration
of the interest
in avoiding
pregnancy
very difficult
in
some
cases.
Finally, current
law ignores
the interest
in family stability
that the
severely
disabled
person shares
with
her parents.
Under
the paternalism
model, the
parents' interest
in convenience,
reduced anxiety,
and family
stability
is not
only deemed
irrelevant
to the
decision,
but is presumed
to
conflict
with the
child's interest.
This
presumption
is valid
if an interest
in procreation
exists.
If no
such interest
exists,
however,
ignoring
the
importance
of family
stability for the
severely retarded
person may
well
lead to
a decision contrary
to her best interest.
The
analysis proposed
here offers
an alternative
conception
of the
interests
of the mentally
retarded person
for whom
sterilization is
proposed.
The
autonomy
model
defines
the interests
of the
mentally
disalled
person
in making
her own reproductive
decisions
more broadly
and more precisely
than does
the paternalism
model. The
competent
person's
interest
in independent
decisionmaking
rests on her
ability to
make
the underlying
reproductive
choice,
whether or
not she
can imple-
ment
that choice
through
a medical
decision.
The model
suggests
that
the
individual who
is not capable
of making autonomous
reproductive
decisions
has an interest
in preserving
family
stability,
and that
this interest
will
be promoted by
state deference
to parental authority.
Thus,
in
contrast to the
paternalism model,
which offers
elaborate substantive
cri-
teria,
the autonomy
model identifies
the correct
allocation of
decisionmaking
authority
as
the
means
of advancing
the
retarded
person's
interests.
The
autonomy
model indicates
that
the interests
of the
mentally
retarded
person will
be best protected
by a legal
rule that limits
protective
state intervention
and supports
private
decisionmaking
by the
individual
or,
if she is incompetent
to make
the reproductive
decision,
by
her parents.
The next
Part examines
the implications
of the autonomy
model for
the formulation
of
an optimal
legal rule.
138. See
supra note
50.
139.
The person
incapable of
making her own
choices has
an interest
in having parents
make
decisions for
her and in avoiding
state interference.
In analyzing the
child's interest in parental
authority
under the
constitutional family
privacy doctrine,
Garvey aptly
asserts that
"[c]onstitutional
liberties protect
children
in the exercise
of choices that
their parents
have made
for
them." Garvey,
supra note
100, at 1782.
1 39
DUKE
LAW JOURNAL
III. APPLICATION OF THE AUTONOMY MODEL
A.
Protecting
Meaningful
Choice-The
Retarded
Person
as Decisionmaker.
Devising
a legal rule that
protects the
expansively
defined autonomy
interest of
the competent
retarded
individual
is
more difficult
than
it
might
first appear.
The
autonomy
model
suggests that
three
separate
inquiries
are
relevant:
an inquiry
into the
individual's
competency
to
make
the decision
to have
children,
an inquiry
into her
competency
to
avoid
pregnancy,
and
an inquiry
into
her competency
to
elect sterilization.
The examination
of
competency
is further
complicated
in this context
by
the
unique
relevance
of
the
person'sfuture
competency
and
interest
in
autonomous
choice. Because
sterilization
extinguishes
repro-
ductive
capacity
and moots
the issue
of reproductive
choice,
the
law
should
preserve
the
disabled person's
potential
interest
in making
her
own decisions
if she
might
become competent
in
the future.
Thus
a determination
of
incompetency
may
require
an
evaluation
of future
functioning
that
is necessarily
speculative
in
nature.
Because
incompetency
may be
due to developmental
factors,
potential
competency
is
particularly
important
if
the
mentally
retarded
person
is
a minor.
To
guard against
error,
sterilization
might
be restricted
to
adults.
14°
However,
because
severely
retarded
minors have
a strong
interest
in
family
continuity,
they may
particularly
benefit
from legal
sup-
port for
parental
authority;
a policy
that proscribes
their
sterilization
may not
serve their
interests.
Despite
uncertainty,
it is possible
to make
a
determination
that
some severely
disabled
minors
will never
have the
capacity
to make
reproductive
decisions
independently.
A person
also has
an interest
in preserving
future
options
if she
is
competent
but
currently
has no
expressed
preferences.
Thus,
the re-
tarded
person who
is potentially
a capable
parent
should
not be sterilized
on
the ground that
she has expressed
no desire
for children.
Only her
stable
long-term
desire
not to
have children
should
be implemented
through
sterilization.
When
parents
propose
sterilization
for
a mentally
retarded
child, an
evaluation
by
an expert
in mental
retardation
is necessary.
One
source of
erroneous
sterilization
decisions
in the
past was
reliance
on the attending
physician's
opinion
that
sterilization
was medically
appropriate.
This
140. In most
states, normal
minors
may not obtain
sterilization
because of
the permanency
of
the procedure.
Sterilization
laws directed
at mentally
disabled
persons require
a determination
of
future
incompetency,
see supra
note 34, thereby
distinguishing
the mentally
retarded
minor from
other
presumably incompetent
normal minors.
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
physician
was usually a gynecologist
with little or no expertise in
assessing
the functional
capabilities of mentally disabled
persons. Some current
laws
attempt to remedy this problem
by requiring psychiatric,
psychological, or "social" evaluation of the retarded individual. 1
However,
little guidance is given regarding the focus of the evaluation or the
required
expertise of the evaluator.
Most physicians, including
psychiatrists,
have very limited expertise
in mental retardation; most
psychologists
have
only marginally more.
A specific designation of expertise
and
training in mental retardation would promote more accurate assessments
of competency than
are likely to result under
current law.
The determination of whether the disabled individual has the ability
to make her own reproductive
decisions should begin with
an evaluation
of her interest in procreation. Then, if she does not want children, the
competency of this choice
must be assessed. If her decision
to avoid
pregnancy is competently made, further inquiry is necessary to determine
whether she is capable of making the informed medical decision to implement
her
reproductive choice. The discussion that follows examines the
implications of positive and negative findings of competency.
1. Parenting Capacity and Reproductive Choice. The autonomy
model presumes an interest in procreation, unless the individual would
be so limited in her parenting ability that the state would be justified in
terminating her parental
rights should she ever have
a child. Thus,
under the autonomy
model, the individual who
is capable of functioning
as a minimally adequate parent will not be sterilized unless she compe-
tently chooses never to have children. Making a determination about
parenting
ability will admittedly be difficult
unless the person has had
substantial
experience
being
with
children.'
4
2
A person has the minimal capacity to function as a parent if she
would be
able to meet a child's most basic
needs. Thus, a parent must
be
able to understand the child's basic nutritional requirements and protect
141. See supra note 38.
142. The assessment
of present competency to make
a decision is potentially a highly reliable
judgment. It can be compared with determinations about competency of criminal defendants to
stand trial. See R. ROESCH & S. GOLDING, COMPETENCY TO STAND TRIAL (1980). Much more
uncertain are evaluations that
predict how someone will function or
act in the future. See J.
MONAHAN, PREDICTING VIOLENT BEHAVIOR: AN ASSESSMENT OF CLINICAL TECHNIQUES
(1981); Melton & Scott, supra note 122, at 39.
Several types of inquiry may be useful in assessing potential parental competency. An assess-
ment of the person's
actual and potential ability to care
for herself is important because the person
who cannot
provide for her own nutritional, health, and
safety needs cannot assume responsibility
for another person. The individual's experience in caring for her own children, her siblings, or
neighborhood children is also significant. Problem-solving hypotheticals involving typical child care
issues may also be useful.
41
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
the
child from physical
harm.
She must be able
to discern illness
and
know how
to obtain medical
help; she
should also be
able to express
affection and
provide adequate
supervision
of the child's
daily routine.
The retarded
person's interest
in having
children, however,
should
not
be contingent
on her ability
to perform other
functions usually
asso-
ciated
with being a
"good" parent.
1 43
If she must
demonstrate
a more
sophisticated
capability
to provide
intellectual
stimulation
or meet the
child's
emotional
needs,
she will be
subject to
standards
of competency
in
parenting that
are not applied
to others.
Although good
parents typi-
cally provide
an
intellectually
stimulating
environment,
many normal
parents do
not. Horizontal
equity
thus
dictates that
nothing
more than
a
standard
of
minimal
adequacy
be required.
The individual
who
is not
capable of
functioning
as a
parent has
no
interest
in procreation
and the choice
to have children
is not available
to
her. Arguably,
she
might have
the capability
to
choose among
alternatives
for
avoiding
pregnancy;
if
so,
her
competent
preferences
should
be
respected.
It
is unlikely,
however,
that a person
who
is incapable
of be-
ing a minimally
adequate
parent
because
of mental
retardation
will
have
the
cognitive
ability to
consider contraceptive
alternatives
and
make an
informed
medical
decision.
144
If she is incompetent,
a decision
will be
made for her
by her parents
or (in
some cases)
by a court.
2. Protecting
the
Decision to
Avoid Pregnancy:
Reproductive
Choice
and the
Medical Decision.
A mentally
disabled
person may
clearly
and
unambiguously
express
a desire
not to have
children.
If she understands
the implications
of
the decision
and if
it is made
without
coercive influ-
ence, her
expressed
preference
should
be respected
by the
law as a
com-
143. The
findings of
research assessing
the parental
capability
of mentally
disabled persons
are
mixed. This
research involves
only parents
who are mildly
or moderately
retarded.
Some observers
have suggested
that the
children of
mentally retarded
parents
may suffer from
a lack of intellectual
stimulation.
See E. SCHULMAN,
supra note
26, at 302.
An early study
of mentally
disabled parents
found that
42% provided
adequate
care for their
children's physical
needs, 32%
provided
marginal
care, and 26%
provided care warranting
removal. See
Mickelson, The Feebleminded
Parent:
A
Study of90 Family
Cases,
51 AM. J. MENTAL
DEFICIENCY
644, 645
(1947). Some
researchers have
observed
that although
mentally retarded
parents
may not provide
care meeting
"middle class"
standards,
most
do provide adequate
care. See Murphy,
Coleman & Abel,
Human Sexuality
in the
Mentally
Retarded,
in TREATMENT
ISSUES AND
INNOVATIONS
IN MENTAL
RETARDATION
615 (Q.
Matson
& F. Andrasik
eds. 1983).
Support
services may
be available
to provide
parents with
training and
assistance. See
Mickelson,
supra, at
644. Rosenberg
and MeTate
reported that
mildly retarded
persons
who participated
in parent
training programs
were able
to improve
their parenting
skills. Rosenberg
& McTate,
supra
note 30, at 24, 37.
144.
If such a hypothetical
person
existed,
her interest might
be characterized
as an
interest in
controlling the
health care
decision, rather
than an interest
in controlling
the reproductive
decision.
In
any event it would be
a restricted exercise
of autonomy since she
is not free to choose
the alterna-
tive of
having
children.
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
petent
and meaningful
reproductive
choice.
Evaluation
of the
competency
of
this decision
should
focus on the
consistency,
clarity,
and
stability
of the expressed
choice and on
the extent to
which the decision
is
an independent
one.
If the
disabled
person
is
found to
be making
a
meaningful
decision
to terminate
permanently
her
ability
to
have children,
an
examination
of
her competency
to make
an
informed
medical
decision
regarding
sterili-
zation
should
follow.
The predominant
standard
defining
competency
to
make
medical
decisions,
and
the
one applicable
to sterilization
decisions,
is the
appreciation
standard.
145
This
standard
requires
an inquiry
into
whether
the individual
has an
inferential
and
factual
understanding
of
the
procedure's
purpose,
consequences,
risks,
and
benefits,
as well
as an
appreciation
of the
contraceptive
alternatives
available
to her.
The
evaluation
of competency
should focus
on the
person's
understanding
of
the
following:
(a)
the
contraceptive
purpose
of
sterilization,
(b)
the
nature
of
the
procedure
(the
incision,
hospitalization,
use
of
anesthesia),
(c)
the
permanence
of reproductive
incapacity
following
sterili-
zation,
(d)
the risks
associated
with the
procedure
(pain,
possible
infection
or
other
complications),
and
(e)
the availability
and
important
characteristics
of nonpermanent
forms
of contraception.
146
The individual
must
be
provided
with
sufficient
information
about
the
proposed
ster-
ilization
to make
an informed
decision;
a finding
of incompetency
should
be based
not
on a
lack of
knowledge,
but
only on
incapacity
to
understand
the
necessary
information.
The
doctrine
of informed
consent
requires
that
the decision
be voluntary
as
well
as competent
and informed.
147
Given
the
potential
conflict
of
interest
between
parent
and
child,
the
dependence
of
the in-
dividual
on her
parents,
and
the observed
suggestibility
of
retarded
persons,
parental
overbearance
may
be
a
significant
possibility.
Therefore,
the independence
of
the individual's
preferences
as
well as
the extent
to
which
her
choices
have been
influenced
by others
must
be determined.
A
determination
regarding
the
individual's
competency
to
make
the
medical
decision
should
be made
as accurately,
but as
unobtrusively,
as
possible.
A nonjudicial
review
of the
finding
that the
person
has compe-
tently
decided
on
sterilization
may
often
be desirable;
however,
it should
be
undertaken
in such
a way
as
to minimize
intrusion
into
the
person's
145. See
supra note
113 and
accompanying
text.
146. See
Melton
& Scott, supra
note
122, at 38-39.
The
most critical
factor
and the one
most
mentally
disabled
persons are
unlikely
to understand
is
irreversibility.
See
infra note
149.
147.
See Meisel,
Roth &
Lidz, Toward
a Model
of the Legal
Definition
of Informed
Consent.
134
Am. J. PSYCHIATRY
285, 286
(1977).
privacy.
1 48
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
Further
inquiry is warranted
only if
competency to
make the
medical
decision
is questionable.
Some persons
may be capable of making
a competent decision not
to
have
children but incapable
of making
an informed
medical decision.
A
person
who is unable
to think abstractly
about
decisionmaking
in the
remote
future might not
fully understand
that sterilization
results in
permanent
infertility;
she
may, however,
have unambiguously
stated
over
an
extended period
of time that
she does not want
to have children.
This
person
may be making a meaningful
reproductive choice never
to have
children; the inference can
be drawn that permanence is desired.
Nonetheless,
in
those
states
that
follow
the
paternalism
model, her
inability to
understand the
concept of permanence would
preclude a competent med-
ical decision
and thus foreclose the possibility
of sterilization, particu-
larly
if
she
already
has
children.
1
49
3. Protecting
Against Erroneous
Decisions.
The more
expansive
recognition
of the autonomy
interest
of retarded
persons under
the autonomy
model
may
arguably increase
the risk of
erroneous decisions
to
sterilize.
The acquiescent
or well-coached
person
might erroneously
be
characterized
as making a meaningful
decision to opt for sterilization.
An
error of this kind
is particularly
costly if the
person has an
interest in
procreation.
5
0
A few safeguards will
reduce this risk. A comprehensive
evaluation
of the individual's
decision
by an expert
in mental retardation
is essen-
tial.
15
'
If the person is
incompetent to
make the medical
decision, a
determination
that
sterilization
is the optimal
means of
implementing
her
competent reproductive choice
should be made. If she is
potentially a
competent
parent, sterilization
is
usually appropriate
only if a
normal
person
in similar
circumstances
would choose
this alternative.
A
mechanism
should be provided
to review
the findings
of competency
and
to determine the
appropriateness
of sterilization
to implement
the choice.
Given the reproductive
interest
at stake, a
judicial proceeding
may be
warranted.
A less costly
and less
intrusive alternative
would be
review
148.
See supra
notes 129-30,
174.
149. For
example, the patient
described supra note
114 had consistently
said for years that
she
wanted "no more babies." There
was no indication that she would ever
change her mind. She could
not, however,
think abstractly
and hypothetically
about how she might
feel in the distant
future.
When asked "What
if you should change
your mind in ten
years?," she would
only repeat the
assertion
that she wanted a
boyfriend and "no more babies."
150. See supra note 90.
151. Many current
sterilization laws require evaluation
by an expert. See supra note 38.
152. See supra notes 83-87.
[Vol. 1986:806
1 52
STERILIZATION
by
a committee
modeled
on a hospital
ethics
committee.
Vol. 1986:806]
153
Finally,
since
informed
consent
to the
medical
procedure
must be
provided
by somecompetent
person,
the
parents'
consent
should
be required.
4. Summary.
When parents
seek
to have
their child
sterilized,
an
expert
in mental
retardation
should
examine
the child
and assess
her
ca-
pacity
to make
reproductive
choices
for herself.
First,
the
expert
should
assess
her
interest
in having
children.
If
she has
the ability
to
provide
minimally
adequate
care for
a child,
no further
inquiry
is
needed;
sterili-
zation
should
be
proscribed
unless
she
expresses
a clear
and independent
preference
not to have
children.
If she lacks
an interest
in procreation,
the
choice to
have
children
will be
unavailable
to
her. In
most
cases, a
decision will
be made
for her
as an incompetent.
If the
individual
expresses
a preference
not to
have
children,
the
second
stage
of
inquiry
begins
with an
examination
of her
capacity
to
make this
decision
autonomously.
If
her preference
represents
a rational
choice,
examination
of
her ability
to
make
the implementing
informed
medical
decision
should
follow.
If she
is competent,
she should
be
treated
like a
normal
person.
If she
is not,
further
assessment
may
be
needed
to probe
the stability
and
consistency
of her decision
and to determine
whether
sterilization
represents
an
appropriate
medical
response.
Some
independent
review
of
these latter
decisions
is advisable.
B.
The
Incompetent
Individual:
Who
Decides?
Analysis
under
the autonomy
model
indicates
that
the range
of
indi-
viduals
who
are competent
to make
reproductive
decisions
is broader
than current
law recognizes.
Some persons,
however,
will have
no inter-
est in
procreation
and
will
be unable
to make
their
own
reproductive
choices.
Under
the paternalism
model,
they will
be subject
to
courts
as
decisionmakers;
their
parents
are
legally
disqualified
because
of
a presumed
conflict
of
interest.
The autonomy
model
indicates
that
the se-
153. For a discussion
of the
function of
hospital ethics
committees
and the recommended
role
of
this type
of committee
when
parents
make decisions
for incompetents,
see infra
note 174 and
accom-
panying text.
There
are three situations
in which
some kind
of independent
review
of the competency
deter-
mination
may be indicated:
1)
The retarded
person is found
competent
to make
the medical
decision and
chooses
sterilization.
2) The
retarded person
is found
competent
to make the
reproductive
but not the
medical
decision,
her
decision
is never
to have children,
and
sterilization
appears
to best
implement
her
choice.
3)
The retarded
person is
incompetent
to make the
reproductive
decision and
her parents
seek authority
to
make the
sterilization
decision.
In choosing
the kind
of review
process,
interests in
individual
and family
privacy
as well as
accuracy
are relevant.
See
supra notes
120-37
and
accompanying
text.
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
verely
impaired individual lacks
an interest in having children;
in such
case there is no
significant conflict
of interest
and a legal rule
promoting
family privacy
and supporting
parental
authority will
best protect
her
interests.
Paternalistic
judicial intervention
should occur
only when
nec-
essary to ensure that
the retarded individual's rights
are not violated.
It is for good
reason that the
law traditionally
recognizes
parents as
decisionmakers for children.
1 54
No one else knows the child
as well or
cares
about her as much as do her
parents. Although most adults
no
longer need their
parents to make decisions for
them, the rationale sup-
porting parental authority
can still be valid with respect
to incompetent
adults.
1 55
For children
and for many incompetent adults,
substitution of
a nonparent
as decisionmaker
is beneficial
only if there
is a serious conflict
of
interest
between
parent
and
child.156
154.
There is a strong tradition of legal support
for parents' authority to make decisions
for their
children
and to generally direct
their upbringing.
The Supreme Court
has recognized the
constitutional
status
of the interest in family privacy,
and has upheld parental authority against
state inter-
vention in several decisions.
See Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S.
205, 234 (1972) (right of Amish
parents to withdraw children
from school at age 14, though legal minimum
age was 16); Pierce v.
Society of Sisters, 268
U.S. 510, 534 (1925) (statute requiring
that all children be sent to public
schools
unreasonably interfered with the "liberty
of parents and guardians to direct the
upbringing
and
education of children under their control");
Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 399
(1923) (stat-
ute forbidding
the teaching of foreign
languages before the
eighth grade unreasonably
interfered with
the
right to "establish a home
and bring up children").
The
state may intervene to protect children
if the parents' decisions or conduct threatens
harm
to the child. See
Prince v. Massachusetts,
321 U.S. 158,
166 (1944) (statute prohibiting
minor from
selling
newspapers and prohibiting adult from
furnishing minor with newspapers did
not infringe
fourteenth amendment
protected liberty).
The state's parens
patriae interest
in the welfare of chil-
dren supports state intervention in cases of abuse and neglect.
There
has been a considerable
amount of
scholarly commentary
on the tension between
family
privacy and the state's
interest in protecting children. See J. GOLDSTEIN,
A. FREUD & J. SOLNIT,
BEFORE THE
BEST INTERESTS OF THE CHILD 28-133
(1979); R. MNOOKIN, CHILD, FAMILY AND
STATE 29-64 (1978);
Wald, Children's Rights: A Framework for
Analysis, 12 U.C. DAVIS L. REV.
225, 281 (1979).
In the first half of this century the rise
of the juvenile court system and social work
movement
created enthusiasm
for state intervention
to protect children.
See generally
M. LEVINE &
A.
LEVINE, A SOCIAL
HISTORY OF HELPING
SERVICES 46-47 (1970);
A. PLATr, THE
CHILD SAV-
ERS: THE INVENTION OF DELINQUENCY
45 (1977). But modern commentators
have challenged the
notion
that children benefit
when the state
intervenes to protect
them from their parents.
See J.
GoI.DSTEIN, A. FREUD & J. SOLNIT,
supra, at 9; Chambers, The "Legalization"
of the Family:
Toward a Policy of Supportive Neutrality.
18 U. MICH. J.L. REF. 805, 817 (1985);
Mnookin, Foster
Care-In Whose
Best Interest?, 43 HARV.
EDUC. REV. 599,
622-26 (1973); Wald,
27 STAN. L. REV.
985, 987-89 (1975).
In recent years there
has also been a recognition that the child
herself may have an interest in
controlling decisions,
particularly reproductive
decisions,
that affect her life.
See supra note 104.
Thus,
legal policy dealing
with children may
on some issues have
to balance three
interests: tile
state's parens patriae interest, the parents'
(and child's) interest in family privacy,
and tile child's
autonomy
interest. See
Garvey, Child, Parent,
State and the Due
Process Clause: An
Essay on the
Supreme
Court's Most Recent Work,
51 S. CAL. L. RIFV. 769
(1978).
155. See inifra
notes 171-72 and
accompanying text.
156. See infra notes
160-69 and accompanying
text.
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
1. Examining
the Conflict of Interest.
A constricted range of
interests
are at stake for a severely disabled person when her parents pro-
pose sterilization. This person will never function as a parent. Meaningful
decisions
about reproduction or
about the medical means
for
avoiding pregnancy are beyond her capabilities. Thus, no interest in selfdetermination
or in reproduction is potentially in conflict with her parents'
interest in seeking sterilization. The severely retarded person does,
however, have an interest in
avoiding pregnancy. The physical
strain of
pregnancy and the discomfort, pain, and risk of childbirth are burdens to
be avoided when the individual cannot enjoy or adequately care for a
baby. Indeed, when a severely retarded young woman is at risk of becoming
pregnant, few question either her interest in avoiding pregnancy
or her parents' authority to protect her by employing some form of contraception.
Beyond this, the severely impaired person has an interest in
avoiding unnecessary medical risk; any surgical or medical procedures
should be beneficial to
her, and risk, discomfort, and
intrusiveness should
be minimized. She also has a right to be treated with dignity. Her objec-
tions should be taken seriously, and her privacy should not be unduly
sacrificed. Finally, her interest in family functioning will often be impli-
cated because
sterilization of he severely
retarded person can lighten the
burden of responsibility on her parents or contribute to their determination
to continue to care for her at home.
For persons who will never have an interest in reproduction, a substantial
conflict
of interest with their
parents is likely only if the
parents
seek to have a hysterectomy performed. The convenience to parents of
avoiding menstrual hygiene care may clash with the child's interest in
avoiding the substantial risk and intrusiveness that attends this surgical
procedure. If the parents
propose a less intrusive form
of sterilization for
their severely impaired
child, no significant conflict
of interest is apparent.
Indeed, this child and her parents have a mutual interest in avoiding
the child's pregnancy and promoting family stability. Furthermore, the
child's interest in minimizing medical risk is served as well, or nearly as
well, by sterilization as it would be by alternative contraceptive options.
2. The Costs of Withholding Parental Authority. The rigorous
procedural and substantive requirements under current law impose formidable
costs on the family, in terms of money, time expended, and psy-
chological stress. In most states, parents seeking sterilization will have to
hire an attorney to pursue
their objective.
57
They may have
to pay for
157. Most parents will need the assistance of a lawyer to file the petition and present supporting
evidence.
Although most laws provide for the
appointment of a guardian ad litem for
the child.
none provides the parent with legal assistance.
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
mental
health
evaluations
and
will
often
be
forced
to miss
time
from
work.
Furthermore,
to
the
extent
that
the
procedure
imposes
burden-
some
requirements
and
particularly
if
it has
an
adversarial
character,
it
will
predictably
create
greater
tension
within
a
family
unit
already
sub-
ject
to considerable
stress.
Many
parents
who
have
struggled
with
the
burden
of caring
for
a
severely
disabled
child
will
understandably
resent
a
judicial
proceeding
that
is
premised
on
the
notions
that
they
are
pursuing
their
own
interest
in seeking
their
child's
sterilization
and
that
a judge
can better
decide
what
is
best
for
their
child.
If sterilization
is
denied
because
rigorous
substantive
requirements
are not
met,
the
parents'
frustration
can
have
a
disruptive
effect
on
their
ability
to
care
for
the child.
For
some
parents,
fear
that
their
child
may
become
pregnant
will
severely
strain
their
ability
to
cope
with
the
difficulties
of
caring
for
a
retarded
child.
Sterilization
may
be
a
means
of
preserving
family
functioning
by
helping
parents
meet
their
responsibilities;
they
may
view
it
as
an alternative
to institu-
tionalization
or
foster
care.
1
58
For
severely
impaired
individuals
whose
parents
propose
a nonintrusive
type
of
sterilization,
judicial
scrutiny
serves
only
one
useful
pur-
pose.
A check
is needed
to ensure
that
the individual
actually
lacks
any
reproductive
autonomy
interest.
It is
possible
to accomplish
this objec-
tive with
less cost
to
the
family
and
the
disabled
person
than
is the
case
under
current
law.
Indeed,
as
I shall
argue
below,
some
individuals
can
receive
adequate
protection
with
no
judicial
proceeding.
Along
with
costly
procedural
protections,
current
law
imposes
burdensome
substantive
barriers.
These
include
requirements
that
no
tem-
porary
form
of
contraception
be workable,
that
the
individual
be
currently
engaging
in
sexual
activity,
and
that
sterilization
be necessary
to
preserve
the physical
or
mental
health
of the
individual.
These
criteria
are
based
on
the assumption
that
a significant
reproductive
interest
is
threatened
by the
sterilization
initiative.
As applied
to
a category
of persons
without
this
interest,
these
requirements
become
superfluous
and
serve
to
thwart
parental
efforts
without
offering
a
corresponding
benefit
to the
child.
Thus,
they
can
ultimately
do more
harm
than
good
to
the
disabled
person.
The
preservation
of
family
functioning
and
the
minimization
of
stress
are
as important
to
the
severely
disabled
person
as to
her parents.
To the
extent
that
the
procedural
and
substantive
requirements
under
158. In
cases
evaluated
at
the Forensic
Psychiatry
Clinic
at
the University
of
Virginia,
parents
often
expressed
frustration
and
resentment
at the
expense
and complex
legal requirements
for
sterili-
zation
and occasionally
have
said
that they
would
give
up custody
if
sterilization
were
not
possible.
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
current law place additional
stress on the family, they represent
a cost to
the
subject of the
sterilization
initiative as
well as to her
parents.
3. The
Constitutional
Parameters:
Parental
Authority and
Children's
Reproductive
Rights.
The
traditional
legal
authority
of
parents
to
make medical
decisions for their
children rests,
in part, on a
presumption
that
parents are
motivated
to promote
their
children's
interests.
If
parental authority
conflicts
with an important
interest
of the child's,
it
should
be
withdrawn.
Courts
and commentators,
emphasizing
the potential
for a conflict
of interest,
have suggested
that the retarded
person's constitutional
interest
in reproductive
privacy
is not protected
unless parental
authority is
withdrawn.1
5 9
It might be
thought that
the autonomy
model
violates
this
interest by
allowing parents
to make the sterilization
decision
for severely
impaired children.
Yet the
critical interest
in reproductive
autonomy
that
mandates
protection
is absent
in these
cases and
consequently
there
is no substantial
ground
for withdrawal
of parental
authority.
The Supreme
Court
has examined
constitutional
challenges to
parental
authority
to make sensitive
medical
decisions for
the child in two
contexts-abortion
and psychiatric
hospitalization.
In both
areas, an im-
portant interest
of the child
may conflict
with the parents'
interest, and
the presumption
underlying
parental authority-that
parents
will act in
their child's
best interest-is
called into
question. These
cases are often
pointed to
by those
who support
withdrawal
of parental
authority
in the
sterilization
context.
However,
an examination
of the Court's
analysis
in
the abortion
and psychiatric
hospitalization
cases supports
the contention
that
a
constitutional
challenge
to
parental
authority
to make
the decision
to
sterilize
a severely
retarded child
has little
merit.
a. The
Abortion Rights
of
Minors.
The mature
minor
who seeks
an abortion
is making
a meaningful
reproductive
choice
that should
be
respected.
Indeed,
under my analysis,
this recognition
should
not be
contingent on
her capacity to
give informed
consent to the
medical pro-
cedure.
Unless undue
coercion is involved,
her decision
not to continue
the pregnancy
warrants
the withdrawal
of traditional
parental
authority.
160
The
abortion cases
present a situation
in which
parents and child
are
in
actual disagreement
over the
decision to
abort, or
in which
the child is
159. See In
re C.D.M., 627 P.2d
607, 614 (Alaska
1981); In re A.W.,
637 P.2d 366, 370
(Colo.
1981); In re Grady,
85 N.J. 235, 264,
426 A.2d 467, 482
(1981); Murdock, supra
note 10, at 932-34;
Price & Burt,
supra note 25,
at 69-70; Sherlock
& Sherlock, supra
note 10, at 955.
160.
A determination
that she is too immature
to make this decision
may lead to the
paradoxical
result
that her pregnancy
should
continue and
the immature
minor should
become
a mother.
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
reluctant to consult her
parents because she fears
conflict.
' Furthermore,
other
interests
besides
health
are
at
stake
here
and
a
congruence
of
interests
between
parent
and
child
cannot
be
presumed.
Therefore,
the
traditional
presumption
that
parents
will
make
medical
decisions
that
promote
their
child's
health
must
be set
aside.
It is
the
possible
conflict
of
interest
and
probable
conflict
in
fact
between
parent
and
child
over
a
matter
of
critical
importance
to the
child's
life,
as well
as the
assumption
that
the
child
is
mature
and
making
a
rational
choice,
that
justifies
the
withdrawal
of
parental
authority.
In
Planned
Parenthood
v.
Danforth,
162
the
Court
rejected
the
notion
that
absolute
parental
authority
over
a
minor's
abortion
decision
could
be
justified
on
the
basis
of
an
interest
in
preserving
family
stability:
It
is difficult
...
to
conclude
that
providing
a
parent
with
absolute
power
to
overrule
a
determination,
made
by
the physician
and
his
minor
patient,
to
terminate
the
patient's
pregnancy
will
strengthen
the
family
unit.
Neither
is it
likely
that
such
veto
power
will
enhance
parental
authority
...
where
the
minor
and
the
nonconsenting
parent
are
so
fundamentally
in
conflict
and
the
very
existence
of
the
pregnancy
already
has
fractured
the
family
structure.
163
A
mildly
disabled
individual
whose
parents
seek
sterilization
has
an
interest
in making
autonomous
reproductive
choices
similar
to that
of a
minor
contemplating
abortion.
However,
the
analogy
is not
applicable
to
a
retarded
person
who
is
so
disabled
that
she
lacks
the
ability
to
make
the
decision.
These
cases
typically
arise
in a
context
that
differs
substantially
from
that
of
the
teenager
seeking
an
abortion
without
her
parents'
knowledge.
If
the
child
is
significantly
retarded,
it
is probable
that
her
parents
have
initiated
the
procedure;
the
child's
response
is
likely
to
be
incomprehension
or
assent.
Since
the
child
has
no
interest
in
reproduction,
there
is
no
potential
conflict
of
interest
with
her
parents
unless
an
intrusive
sterilization
procedure
is
proposed.
The
overt,
or
at
least
implicit,
family
conflict
inherent
in
the
abortion
context
is
absent
here.
Thus,
the
sterilization
decision
is not
made
in
the
context
of
the
"fractured"
family
structure
discerned
by
the
Court
in
Danforth.
Indeed,
the
sterilization
initiative
might
represent
an
effort
by
the
parents
to preserve
161.
In a study
of 1170
teenagers
who
obtained
abortions,
the
Alan
Guttmacher
Institute
found
that
approximately
55%
reported
that
their
parents
were
aware
of
their
decision
to
abort.
Of
those
whose
parents
did
not
know,
23%
said
they
would
not
have
gone
to
an abortion
clinic
if
they
had
been
required
to
tell their
parents;
40%
of
these
said
they
would
have
obtained
an
illegal
abortion.
See
Torres,
Forrest
&
Eisman,
Telling
Parents:
Clinic
Policies
and Adolescents'
Use
of Family
Plan-
ning
and
Abortion
Services,
12 FAM.
PLAN.
PERSP.
284
(1980).
Some
studies
have
suggested
that
minors
overestimate
the
negativity
of parents'
reactions.
See
Furstenburg,
The
Social
Consequences
of Teenage
Parenthood,
8
FAM.
PLAN.
PERSP.
148
(1976).
Nonetheless,
fears
can
affect
the
minor's
behavior.
162.
428
U.S.
52
(1976).
163. Id.
at
75.
16
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
family
functioning
and
thereby
continue to
meet their
responsibilities
toward
their
retarded
child,
an objective
that
surely promotes
the
interest
of the retarded person.
b. The
Analogy
to Psychiatric
Hospitalization.
The
efforts of
parents
to obtain
sterilization
for
their retarded
child
are also
analogous
to
the efforts
of parents
seeking
to have their
reluctant
child
committed
to a
psychiatric
hospital.
Involuntary
psychiatric
hospitalization
is a coercive
medical intervention
and the
interests of
the parents
can conflict
with
a
constitutionally
protected liberty
interest held
by the resisting
child. In
Parham v.
JR., 164 however,
the
Supreme
Court upheld
a Georgia
statute
that
authorized
parents
to place
their minor
children
in psychiatric
hos-
pitals, refusing
to require
a "formal
adversary
pre-admission
hearing"
to
protect
the child's liberty
interest.
1 65
The Court stated
that "[t]he
fact
that a
child may
balk at
hospitalization
...
does not diminish
the
par-
ents'
authority
to
decide
what
is
best
for
the
child."
166
As
Justice
Brennan
pointed out
in his dissenting
opinion in
Parham,
a
significant
conflict of
interest
is possible
in this situation.
The
parents'
decision
to hospitalize
might
be motivated
by
a desire
to relieve
the family
of
the
burden
of a
disruptive
child. Justice
Brennan
argued
that the
child
whose parents
seek
to surrender
custody
to a state
mental
institution
has,
in effect,
been "ousted
from
his family."'
167
The
hospital
may
serve
as a "dumping
ground"
for children
whose
parents
either cannot
or
will not
continue
to care for
them.'
6
8
Policy reasons
for
maintaining
parental
authority-supporting
the
preservation
of the family
unit
and pro-
tecting
family
privacy-are
less compelling
in
this situation.
The
parents' decision
to sterilize
can pose a greater
threat to
a po-
tentially
competent
child's
constitutionally
protected
interests
than
does
the decision
to hospitalize;
sterilization
is permanent
while
psychiatric
hospitalization
may
be of limited
duration.
However,
if the
child is not
potentially
capable
of reproductive
choice,
she
is less at
risk than
the
child
for whom
hospitalization
is sought.
Parents
seeking
sterilization
are
not trying
to "dump"
their retarded
child.
Their
initiative
may well
164.
442 U.S.
584 (1979).
For a critical
analysis of this
case, see Melton,
Family
and Mental
Hospital
as Myths:
Civil Commitment
of Minors,
in CHILDREN,
MENTAL
HEALTH AND
THE LAW
1983, at
151 (1983).
165.
Parham, 442
U.S. at 603.
166.
Id.
at 604.
167.
Id. at 631
(Brennan,
J.,
dissenting).
168. Id.
at 629 ("The
National
Institute of Mental
Health
recently found
that only
36% of
patients below
age 20 who
were confined
in St. Elizabeth's
Hospital
actually required
such hospitalization.").
The
literature
does
not
support
the
majority's positive
view of
state mental hospitals
and
their potential
benefits
to the unwilling
minor whose
parents seek
her admission.
See Melton,
supra
note
164, at
158-59.
DUKE LAW JOURNAL
be an effort to facilitate her continued care at home. Thus, potential conflicts
of
interest
would seem less
probable in this situation than
when
psychiatric
hospitalization
is proposed.
Preserving parental authority
to make the sterilization
decision for
severely impaired children does not inherently violate a constitutionally
protected interest. The critical reproductive interest that mandates pro-
tection in abortion cases
and in sterilization cases involving
less disabled
persons is absent. Furthermore, the potential for conflict would appear
to be less
threatening than when psychiatric
hospitalization is sought
by
parents-a
decision that the Court
has found may be appropriately
made
by parents and doctors without judicial intervention.
69
Thus, some re-
tention of parental authority in these cases should pass constitutional
muster.
The
interest of both parent and
child in family privacy has
itself
been accorded constitutional protection on both libertarian and utilita-
rian grounds.
170
Sound legal policy limits state intervention in family
affairs
to situations in which there
is a real threat of harm to the
child or
in which there is a significant conflict of interest. A parental decision to
sterilize a severely retarded child for contraceptive purposes by a nonin-
trusive procedure
falls within the traditional
legal and constitutional pro-
tections. Expansive paternalistic
intervention by the
state that does not
protect the child is not a valid exercise of parens patriae authority.
Parents who seek sterilization of adult children may seem less
clearly suitable as decisionmakers. Traditional parental authority ex-
169. The Georgia law upheld in Parham required independent review by the medical director of
the facility of the appropriateness of the admission. What the Court rejected was the need for formal
adversary hearings,
which the Court characterized
as "time-consuming procedural minuets."
Parham, 442 U.S. at 605. The
Court found that requiring a hearing
would be disruptive to the
family and
would discourage parents from seeking
needed treatment. Id. at 605.
170. See supra
note 154. Libertarian support for family
privacy is the extension to the family
unit of a belief in the
primacy of the individual under the due
process clause of the fourteenth
amendment. Within the family, parents are the natural decisionmakers for their minor children.
For an analysis of parental authority to
make medical decisions for children, see
Goldstein, Medical
Care for the Child at Risk- On State
Supervention of Parental Authority, 86 YALE
L.J. 645 (1977).
The
utilitarian position emphasizes not so much
the inviolability of the parents' liberty
interest
as it does the insubstantial quality of the state interest that justifies intervention. The proposition
that children are generally better off if the state does not interfere with the family is supported by
three
arguments. First, it is uncertain when parental
conduct will harm children. Second,
the intervention
may be harmful
because it disrupts the child's life and
family ties. Finally, the alternative
placement offered by the state may be
harmful to the child because it is unclear
that children benefit
from foster-care placements. In sum,
family privacy should receive legal support
because parens
patriae intervention may do more harm than good. Compared with the libertarian, the utilitarian
more readily accepts increased state intervention if it is demonstrably beneficial to children. Com-
pare J. GOLDSTEIN, A. FREUD, A.
SOLNIT & S. GOLDSTEIN, IN THE BEST
INTERESTS OF THE
CHILD (1986) (libertarian approach) with Mnookin, supra note 154 (utilitarian approach).
[Vol. 1986:806
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
tends
only to minors,
unless a guardianship
has
been established.
Furthermore,
the
interest
in
family
continuity
is
often
less compelling,
since
most
adult
children
can
be
expected
to
leave
home
at
some
point.
Nonetheless,
parental authority should
be maintained in cases involving
severely
retarded adults who have
been cared for by parents since
child-
hood. One can assume
that these parents know their
child better than
anyone
else and that they are most
concerned with her interests.
If a
surrogate is needed,
there is no reason to believe
that a court will make
better decisions
than parents
in cases in which
no apparent
conflict of
interest exists.
Even if the disabled individual
may eventually leave home
to live more
independently-an objective
which loving parents might
promote-the
parents are still the
best decisionmakers for their incompetent
child.
4. Safeguarding
Against Erroneous
Decisions.
The primary
barrier
to recognizing parental
authority to make sterilization
decisions is
the concern
that person in question will
be erroneously classified as lacking
an
interest
in
reproductive
autonomy. The principal
justification for
judicial
intervention
is that it reduces
error and
provides optimal
protection
of that interest.
Although this protective approach
imposes significant
costs
on an already burdened
family, it may seem necessary
to
ensure that
an accurate
evaluation of
the individual's
capacities is made.
Under the
autonomy model, there
are two ways to reduce error
without unduly
sacrificing of family privacy.
The first, discussed above,
is to
ensure that determinations
regarding competency are made
by an
expert.
173
The
second involves
linking the scope
of judicial
intervention
to the
level of disability. Error can
be reduced by increasing the
level of
scrutiny and procedural
protection in cases in
which there exists an enhanced
possibility that
the individual has a reproductive
interest.
Mentally disabled persons
who will require lifelong
care clearly lack
the
capacity to care for a child. They
also have a greater interest
in fam-
ily continuity and stability
than do those who are
less disabled. Thus,
only minimal procedural
requirements are desirable.
If a reliable clinical
evaluation
shows that the person lacks
the capacity to care for herself,
little risk is created
by avoiding
a judicial proceeding
altogether
and permitting
the
sterilization
to be performed
upon parental
request and
authorization.
171. See supra notes 101-02 and accompanying text.
172. An objective for many retarded
adults is to live in a home or apartment
with a few other
disabled persons with minimal assistance
and supervision. See E. SCHULMAN,
supra note 26, at 65.
173.
See supra note 151
and accompanying
text.
171
172
DUKE
LAW
JOURNAL
[Vol. 1986:806
In the case of
a less disabled person who
is potentially capable of
caring
for herself, but who clearly
lacks an interest in reproduction,
judi-
cial review
is desirable if the procedural
costs to the individual and her
family are outweighed by the
potential for reducing error.
Alternatively,
procedural
costs might be reduced without
unduly sacrificing accuracy
by
using a less formal review forum
similar to a hospital ethics
commit-
tee.174 Such a committee could undertake nonadversarial review of the
expert's evaluation to ensure that it is competent, independent, and based
on all relevant information.
The committee could
consult with other ex-
perts or with
the parents. Such a nonjudicial
review mechanism would
protect family privacy and stability to a greater degree than would a judicial
proceeding.
If the disability is less severe, the possibility of underestimating the
interest in reproductive choice becomes greater, and the costs of proce-
dural protections become
more acceptable. Thus,
if the findings of the
expert raise any ambiguity about the individual's potential interest in re-
productive choice, judicial review is warranted.
174.
Institutional Review Boards (IRBs) review
proposals for research involving human
subjects
with the objective
of protecting the subjects from undue
harm and ensuring informed consent. Federal
regulations require IRB approval of virtually all federally funded research. See 45 C.F.R.
§ 46.103 (1985). The committee
must be diverse in membership and
must include members from
diverse disciplines
and different medical specialties. See
id. § 46.107. See generally N. HERSHEY
&
R. MILLER, HUMAN EXPERIMENTATION AND THE LAW 47 (1976); R. LEVINE, ETHICS AND REGULATION
OF
CLINICAL RESEARCH 321-63 (1986). For
an analysis of ethics committees and the
law,
see Capron, Legal Perspectives on Institutional Ethics Committees, 11 J.C. & U.L. 417 (1985).
Ethics
committees have been established in
other areas to review or make recommendations
regarding
medical decisions. For example, Infant
Care Review Committees (ICRCs) assist
in decisionmaking
about
critically ill newborns. The
current applicable HHS regulation recommends
that
any
health care provider receiving federal assistance
establish an ICRC. 45 C.F.R.
§ 84.55(a)
(1985). The regulation
includes an advisory model making the
committee responsible for: (I) rec-
ommending institutional
policies concerning the withholding or
withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment
for seriously ill newborns, (2) providing
advice when life-sustaining treatment
is in question,
and (3) reviewing situations where life-sustaining medical or surgical treatment has been withdrawn.
HHS recommends that
the IRCRs include members from varied
backgrounds such as doctors,
nurses,
hospital administrators, lawyers, disability
group representatives, and community
members.
HHS
also recommends that a medical staff member
serve as chairperson. Id. § 84.55(f).
In Bowel)
v. American Hosp. Ass'n, 106 S. Ct.
2101 (1986), the Supreme Court upheld parental
authority to
elect to withhold life-sustaining
treatment from seriously ill newborns
and invalidated four subsec-
tions ofsection 84.55, including the subsection
that required health care institutions
receiving federal
funds to post notice that treatment could
not be withheld from handicapped infants
solely because of
their handicap. 45 C.F.R. § 84.55(b) (1985). Subsections (a) and (f) were not challenged, however.
See Bowen, 106 S. Ct. at 2106 n.4. The American Academy of Pediatrics adopted guidelines for
Hospital Infant Bioethics
Committees in April 1984. See American
Academy of Pediatrics Guidelines
for
Infant
Bioethics
Committees,
II
J.C. & U.L. 433 (1985).
A sterilization-review committee might include mental retardation experts, gynecologists, psychologists,
attorneys, parents, and mental
disability advocates. The committee
should review the
professional assessment
of competency, not decide whether sterilization
is in the individual's best
interest. In performing
its review, it may be necessary
for the committee to speak directly with
the
individual and her parents,
although this may have significant privacy
costs. See supra notes 129-30.
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
Mandatory
judicial
review may also
be indicated
if the person
protests
the
sterilization
in any meaningful
way,
regardless of her
level of
disability.1
75
The incompetent person's
protest should not be a bar
to her
parents'
decision. Nonetheless, it
would justify mandatory judicial
scru-
tiny
of her lack of
competency.
The
autonomy model contemplates
a considerably more limited
ju-
dicial role than does the paternalism
model. Decisions made
outside the
judicial process
will often better
serve the interests
of the disabled
person.
For the seriously disabled individual,
family privacy and stability
will be
promoted by as simple
a review process as is consistent
with an accurate
assessment
of her interests. For
the clearly competent or potentially
competent
person, judicial
review should
only be triggered,
if at all, when
sterilization
is proposed as a means
to implement the choice
to avoid
pregnancy by a person who
lacks the capacity to make
the medical
decision.
There are
only two situations
under the
autonomy model
in which it
is appropriate
for courts
to actually decide
whether sterilization
is in
the
best
interest of the incompetent disabled
person.
The first is when
the
parents seek a hysterectomy
for their child; the
second is when the parents
who are
seeking sterilization
of their child
have not
assumed pri-
176
mary
responsibility
for her care.
In both instances,
the autonomy
model
indicates that the interests of
the individual are such that the
parents can
no longer be presumed to be the best decisionmaker.
a. The Special
Case of Hysterectomy.
Judicial scrutiny
is appropriate
if
a
hysterectomy
is
sought
because
this
operation
subjects
the
individual
to
major
surgery
that
is
not
required
for
gynecological
reasons.1
Parents
may seek a hysterectomy
for a number of reasons. Usually
they
desire
to end their
daughter's menstrual
cycles
because they believe
that
she
is unable to manage menstrual
hygiene tasks. Some parents
may seek
a hysterectomy because their
daughter experiences physical
or psychological
problems
during
menstruation.
178
Finally, parents
may propose a
175.
Some threshold
of understanding may
be required before
judicial review is
triggered; a
young child
or seriously retarded person may protest
a medical procedure without comprehension.
The review is a mechanism to ensure
that the individual has not been wrongly
classified as one who
lacks
reproductive interests.
Responding to
the protest by invoking
the judicial process
signifies that
the individual's
objection is respected. For an analysis
of the importance of process to human
dignity,
see Mashaw, Administrative Due
Process: The Quest for a Dignitary Theory,
61 B.U.L. REV.
885 (1981).
176. See
supra notes 154-56
and accompanying text.
177. See
supra note 126 and
accompanying text.
178.
Parents often report that their retarded
daughters are unduly distressed during their
periods
and are consequently
difficult to manage at home and
at school. Some may even react self-destructively.
Thus,
in some families,
the girl's period may
cause considerable
disruption each month.
In
77
DUKE LAW
JOURNAL
hysterectomy for their own and their daughter's convenience, even if the
child experiences few problems
with menstruation. They
may reason
that since their
disabled daughter will never
want to have children, a
hysterectomy is a desirable
way to avoid the monthly
"hassle" of menstruation.
179
In light of the significant medical risks involved, few normal
women would
consider undergoing a hysterectomy
purely for
convenience. Therefore, a decision
to subject an incompetent
individual
to this
procedure cannot be justified
on such relatively minor
grounds.
The important inquiry
when a hysterectomy is proposed
is whether
the problems associated
with the menstrual
periods substantially inter-
fere with the individual's
functioning and well-being
and, if they do,
whether they are subject
to remediation. Parents
(and even teachers)
often underestimate
the potential for training
mentally disabled girls
to
manage menstrual
hygiene tasks and thus
may exaggerate the burden.1
b.
Petitioning Parents Who Have
Relinquished Care of Their
Child.
The case
for supporting parental authority
to make the sterilization decision
is considerably weakened
if the parents have put the
child in an
institution or surrendered custody to a state agency. These parents may
lack the intimate
concern for and knowledge
about the child which, in
the case of custodial
parents, supports the presumption
that the parents
will act to promote the
child's interest. Furthermore,
there is less reason
to support the authority
of parents who have not
assumed the burdensome
responsibility of
care for the disabled child.
Moreover, some par-
ents in this
situation may petition for
sterilization because of pressure
from the facility
where the child resides. Finally,
the retarded person's
interest in family
continuity and harmony is
not great in this context.
Although
there is less reason to
support parental authority
in these
cases, it does not necessarily
follow that a court will
always be a better
decisionmaker. A court,
however, is less likely than
the parents to be
subject to
external pressures or be influenced
by a conflict of interest
in
this context. A judicial decisionmaker
is arguably preferable
because
there
is no compelling argument
that the child's interest is better
pro-
tected by preserving parental
authority. The court should
make the decision
that a reasonable
and concerned parent would
make to promote the
one Forensic Psychiatry Clinic case, E.'s
mother reported that she was required
to miss three or four
days of work each month when her severely
retarded daughter had her period
because E.s teacher
and sitter found E.'s inability
to manage menstrual hygiene tasks so offensive
that they urged E's
mother to keep her at home during these times.
179. In several of the Forensic Psychiatry
Clinic cases, doctors advised parents
to seek hystereetomy
despite
the absence of serious problems. See supra
note 126 and accompanying text. Parents
sometimes seemed
unaware that hysterectomy
is major surgery.
180. See supra note 127.
[Vol. 1986:806
0
Vol. 1986:806]
STERILIZATION
child's
welfare. Considerations
may include the
likelihood of
sexual activity
and
risk of pregnancy,
the relative
benefits to
this individual
of
alternative forms
of contraception, and the individual's
expressed or anticipated
preferences.
IV.
CONCLUSION
The undisputed objective
of sterilization law is to promote
decisions
that
reflect the interests
of the disabled
person.
The autonomy
model
proposed
in this article
offers a more
accurate and precise
definition
of
these
interests than
does the paternalism
model that
forms the founda-
tion
of current law.
The paternalism
model limits
the mentally
disabled
person's freedom
through
the erection of
formidable barriers
to steriliza-
tion. These barriers are
justified by a strong presumption
that the individual
has
a pervasive
interest, not
in autonomy,
but in procreation.
By
clarifying the
substantive interest
in procreation
as an interest
in producing
a
child
to
rear,
the
autonomy
model
promotes
a
direct
examination
of
whether the person
in fact has
this interest.
If the person
cannot rear a
child, she
lacks this interest
and the law
should take
into account those
interests that
she retains.
These residual
interests include
interests in op-
timal
medical decisions,
in human
dignity and
privacy,
and in
family
stability.
The
desire to correct
the abuses
of the past is
admirable. We
should
only take
care that in pursuing
this goal,
we do not
create a new set
of
problems for
the future. In
contrast to current
law, the autonomy
model
accords
substantial
deference to personal
and family
autonomy.
The
model reveals
that the law's
objectives are
best met by leaving
the sterilization
decision
to the retarded
person who is
competent to make
her own
reproductive choices,
with only
as much intervention
as is
necessary to
facilitate her
decisions. For
retarded persons
who cannot
make their
own decisions,
parents-not courts-are
the best surrogates.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment